impossible to find before the nineteenth century a statement of the nature and purpose of literature that does not include the claim that it promotes virtue or improves the world. In what Tompkins calls "modernist" thinking about literature (which clearly includes a good deal of Romantic and realist thinking as well) it is, on the other hand, difficult to find statements that do. Of course the presence of didactic claims does not mean that the value of the work lies in its didactic function, any more than the fact that so much art, music, and literature was for centuries in the service of the church means that it can only be judged by Christian standards. This is a familiar critical problem, perhaps the most familiar problem of literary criticism, and it does not disappear when we turn to women's writing.
|
There are two central objections to didactic views of literature, both familiar and both, in my view, irrefutable. The pragmatic objection derives from the fact that the purpose of didactic writing lies outside itself: it aims to influence our moral attitudes and even our behavior, to win converts for Christ, to cause us to treat our friends with more consideration, to vote socialist (or conservative), and so on. The site of its success or failure is not confined to the textual experience and may even be independent of it. However enthusiastic our praise of a work's intentions, it will not have succeeded in carrying them out unless it has, in some degree, changed the world. Uncle Tom's Cabin is interesting here, because the case that it succeeded in doing this is probably stronger than with any other novel ever written. Tompkins's claim that critics have denied to the novel "the power to work in and change the world" is quite misleading: criticism has disputed the artistic value of the novel, but conservative and liberal critics alike have agreed about its practical effect. Lincoln's famous compliment to Stowe, as the little lady who started this big war, sounds like evidence that her book succeeded, if not in its direct purpose (for it was not the intention of this pacific writer to start a war), at least in a cognate one. But even this example is not exactly hard evidence, and it is difficult, if not impossible, to demonstrate that the novel did speed up abolition, or that Dickens did speed up any actual social reforms (the evidence, in that instance, points rather against the claim). These may seemindeed arecrude criteria, but unless we locate the site of didactic impact outside the textual experience, we cannot claim that a work is promoting virtue, converting to Christ, or helping to emancipate the slaves.
|
Ideological readings of literature are not of course to be equated with didactic readings, since they do not look at the stated moral purpose of the work but at how the work illustrates the intermeshing of art and power,
|
|