completely or partially prevented from the full possession of or exercise of rights. These included women, young people, the mentally ill, and the prodigal.
65 Children acquired legal personality as soon as they were born, but in order to count as born they had to have lived for at least a moment outside of the womb. According to the Digest , an unborn child was not a human being. 66
|
The Roman term obligatio referred to a personal right, but only as a constraint to cause a person to do something or leave something undone in the interest of someone else. Mostly this had to do with matters of pecuniary value and with patrimonies. As J. Declareuil sees it, these constraintswhether positive or negativeprimarily reveal a jurisprudence that tended to reduce legal relations to an economic plane. 67 Thus rights in Roman law refers primarily to res , to "things." A thing can be a physical object or a debt one is owed, but both property and debts due have in common that they are assets of economic value. When Gaius and Justinian speak of the law of things, they are referring to the part of the law that governs the formation, exchange, and use of economic assets. 68
|
Geoffrey Samuel locates the starting point of the idea of subjective rights in Roman laws of property. He stresses that the history of "right" is complex because it follows more than one philosophical line. One strand of the idea of "natural right" has to do with property and ownership, while the other concerns the more abstract moral basis for constitutional theory. This latter line places more emphasis on natural law, ius , justice, and dominium as universal ideals. 69
|
In part this is an epistemological problem, because the word ius or nomos meant very different things, for example, to Aristotle, Aquinas, and Locke. For Aristotle, the law was a "thing" inevitably intertwined with the polis or state. For Aquinas, ius was objective juridical connection. For Locke, ius was subject to the positive rules of property law. "Thus to compare, even unhistorically," says Samuel, "the concept of a right, or its correlative, in the works of Locke and Aquinas would be to compare two quite distinct structures of legal epistemology." 70
|
|