Infinitesimal: How a Dangerous Mathematical Theory Shaped the Modern World

BOOK: Infinitesimal: How a Dangerous Mathematical Theory Shaped the Modern World
13.97Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

 

The author and publisher have provided this e-book to you for your personal use only. You may not make this e-book publicly available in any way.
Copyright infringement is against the law. If you believe the copy of this e-book you are reading infringes on the author’s copyright, please notify the publisher at:
us.macmillanusa.com/piracy
.

 

To Jordan and Ella

 

CONTENTS

 

Title Page

Copyright Notice

Dedication

Epigraph

Introduction

PART I: THE WAR AGAINST DISORDER: THE JESUITS AGAINST THE INFINITELY SMALL

1. The Children of Ignatius

2. Mathematical Order

3. Mathematical Disorder

4. “Destroy or Be Destroyed”: The War on the Infinitely Small

5. The Battle of the Mathematicians

PART II: LEVIATHAN AND THE INFINITESIMAL

6. The Coming of Leviathan

7. Thomas Hobbes, Geometer

8. Who Was John Wallis?

9. Mathematics for a New World

Epilogue: Two Modernities

Dramatis Personae

Time Line

Notes

Acknowledgments

Index

Also by Amir Alexander

A Note About the Author

Copyright

 

No continuous thing is divisible into things without parts.

—ARISTOTLE

 

Introduction

 

A COURTIER ABROAD

In the winter of 1663 the French courtier Samuel Sorbière was presented at a meeting of the newly founded scientific academy, the Royal Society of London. Sorbière, explained Henry Oldenburg, the Society’s distinguished secretary, was a friend from the dark days of the civil war, when the king was driven out of England and made his court in Paris. Now, three years after Charles II had been restored to his throne in London, Oldenburg was proud to host his old friend in his true home, and to share with him the exciting new investigations taking place under the Royal Society’s roof. For the next three months, Sorbière traveled the land, meeting with political leaders and leading intellectual lights, and even the king himself. Throughout this time, the gregarious Frenchman made the Royal Society his home, attending its meetings and socializing with its fellows. They, for their part, treated him with the greatest respect, and bestowed on him their highest honor: they made him a fellow of the Royal Society.

Whether Sorbière was worthy of this honor is debatable. Although he was a noted physician in his day, and something of a man of letters, even he did not consider himself an original thinker. By his own testimony he was a “trumpeter” rather than a “soldier” in the “warfare of letters,” one who did not promote his own ideas but who advertised the ingenious inventions of other men through his far-flung web of acquaintances and correspondents. And it was, to be sure, an impressive network, including some of the greatest luminaries in France, and philosophers and scientists in Italy, the Dutch Republic, and England. Sorbière was of a type familiar in intellectual circles from that day to ours, the man whom everybody knows, though not necessarily respects all that much. Of greater concern to his hosts, however, was the fact that Sorbière was a close friend and the French translator of Thomas Hobbes, a man most members of the Society considered a dangerous subversive, and a threat to religion and the state.

If the powers that be at the Royal Society were willing to overlook these missteps and invite him into their circle, the reason was simple: Sorbière was a man on the rise. In 1650, after years of living in exile in Holland, he’d returned to France and, four years later, abandoned his Protestant faith and converted to Catholicism. At a time when the position of Protestants in France was becoming increasingly precarious, this was a wise choice. Sorbière became a protégé of Cardinal Mazarin, Louis XIV’s chief minister, and was admitted to the king’s inner circle. He was granted a pension and the title of royal historiographer, and tried to use his influence as a high-ranking courtier to establish a scientific academy in France. His journey to England was meant, in part, as a study of the Royal Society, to determine whether it could serve as a useful model for a similar institution back home. To the grandees of the fledgling Royal Society, always on the lookout for patrons and benefactors, Sorbière was an emissary from the brilliant court of Louis XIV, and hence a man to be treated with the utmost consideration.

If Oldenburg and his fellows hoped to be repaid in kind for the honor they had granted Sorbière, they were quickly disappointed. Mere months after returning home, Sorbière published an account of his experiences in England that showed little appreciation for the country he had so recently visited, stunning his former hosts. In Sorbière’s eyes, England suffered from an excess of religious freedoms and an excess of “Republican spirit,” both of which undermined established religion and royal authority. The official Church of England, Sorbière wrote, was likely the best of the plethora of sects, because its “Hierarchy inspires People with Respect to those who are Supream over them, and is a support to the Monarchy.” But the others—Presbyterians, Independents, Quakers, Socinians, Mennonites, etc.—are the “pernicious” fruit of excessive toleration and have no place in a peaceful realm.

Sorbière, to be fair, did lavish praise on the Royal Society, and spoke with admiration of the experiments conducted in its halls and of the civility of the debates among its members. He even predicted that “if the advance-project of the Royal Society be not some way or other blasted,” then “we shall find a world of people fall into Admiration of so excellent a learned Body.” The details of Sorbière’s account, however, were far less flattering. He claimed that the Society was divided between the followers of two French philosophers, Descartes and Gassendi, an assertion that offended the English on both patriotic and principled grounds; the Royal Society prided itself on following nature alone, eschewing any systematic philosophy. Sorbière insulted the Society’s patron the Earl of Clarendon, Charles II’s Lord High Chancellor, by writing that he understood the formalities of the law, but little else, and had “no knowledge of literature.” Of the Oxford mathematician John Wallis (1616–1703), one of the Society’s founders and leading lights, Sorbière wrote that his appearance inclined one to laughter and that he suffered from bad breath that was “noxious in conversation.” Wallis’s only hope, according to Sorbière, was to be purified by the “Air of the court in London.”

For the Society’s nemesis Thomas Hobbes, however, who was also Wallis’s personal enemy, Sorbière had only praise. Hobbes, he wrote, was a courtly and “gallant” man, and a friend of “crowned heads,” despite his upbringing as a Protestant. Furthermore, Sorbière claimed, Hobbes was the true heir of the illustrious Sir Francis Bacon, the late Lord Chancellor of England and prophet of the new science. This last was the most egregious of Sorbière’s offenses in the eyes of the Royal Society grandees. Bacon was venerated in the Society as its guiding spirit and, effectively, patron saint. To have his mantle bestowed on Hobbes was intolerable. As Thomas Sprat, the Society’s historian, wrote in a thorough rebuttal of Sorbière’s account, there was no more likeness between Hobbes and Bacon than there was “between St. George and the Waggoner.”

Sorbière, as it turned out, paid dearly for his perceived ingratitude to his English hosts. He may have cared little for Sprat’s insults, hurled from faraway London, but he could not ignore the unpleasant ramifications in the royal court in Paris. France at the time sided with England in its war against the Dutch Republic, and Louis XIV was not pleased that one of his own courtiers was causing diplomatic friction with a useful ally. He promptly stripped Sorbière of his status as royal historiographer and banished him from court. Though the banishment was lifted several months later, things were never the same for Sorbière. He repeatedly tried to ingratiate himself with the king, and when that failed, he traveled to Rome to seek the Pope’s patronage instead. He died in 1670, never having regained the status and prestige he had enjoyed on the eve of his journey to England.

Though disastrously ill-timed as far as his career was concerned, Sorbière’s
A Voyage to England
expresses views that in many ways were what one might expect from a man in his position. He was, after all, a courtier to Louis XIV, the king most responsible for establishing royal absolutism in France, and whose philosophy of governance was well encapsulated in his (possibly apocryphal) saying “L’état c’est moi.” In the 1660s Louis was rapidly concentrating state power in royal hands, and was well on his way to creating a single-faith state, a process completed with the expulsion of the Protestant Huguenots in 1685. If the French court’s ambition was to create a nation of “one king, one law, one faith” (“un roi, une loi, une foi”), then certainly Sorbière saw little evidence of that in England. Not only had the English effectively suppressed the true Catholic faith, but they had not even succeeded in replacing it with a single religion of their own. A plethora of sects was undermining the established state religion, and thereby the authority of the king. Personages whose actions during the civil war had suggested dangerous republican tendencies now occupied respectable positions in both church and state, whereas Hobbes, a steadfast royalist whose philosophy supported “crowned heads,” was marginalized.

Nor were things better when it came to the personal manners of Englishmen. In France, membership in court society was the highest social as well as political aspiration of any man or woman eager to leave his or her mark. The members of this exclusive society were distinguished by their fashionable dress and refined manners, all designed to set them apart from outsiders and establish their social superiority. Sorbière’s English hosts, however, showed little inclination to follow the French example. While some of them—including Royal Society president Lord Brouncker and the noble-born Robert Boyle—were members of the high aristocracy, whose upbringing equaled that of any French courtier, others were not. And as was clear in the case of Wallis, a lack of courtly grace did not disqualify one from a place of honor in the highest intellectual circles. Hobbes, in contrast, had spent a lifetime as a member of aristocratic houses, had adopted their manners, and was therefore a man after Sorbière’s own heart. By ridiculing Wallis and praising Hobbes, Sorbière was doing more than merely expressing his personal sensibilities; he was criticizing the lack of courtly refinement in English society and lamenting the fact that, in England, the court did not set the cultural tone of the land as it did in France. When the low mixed with the high, and boors such as Wallis were allowed in high society, what hope was there for court and king to establish their authority? Such mixing would never have been allowed at the court of the Sun King, and only confirmed Sorbière’s opinion that a dangerous “Spirit of Republicanism” was lurking beneath the surface of English society.

Hobbes, in Sorbière’s view, was everything a cultured man should be: courtly in his manners, a friend and companion to the great men of the realm, a steadfast loyal subject, and a philosopher whose teachings (in Sorbière’s opinion) supported the rule of kings. Wallis was quite the opposite: uncourtly and uncouth, and a former Parliamentarian who had made war on his king and who had undeservedly been granted a place of honor by the restored monarch. Little wonder that in the long feud between Wallis and Hobbes, the French monarchist sided with Hobbes. But in his account of their dispute, Sorbière does not dwell on the two men’s political or religious differences, but concentrates on something else entirely: “The Argument,” he explains, “was about the indivisible Line of the Mathematicians, which is a mere Chimera, of which we can have no idea.” For Sorbière, it all boiled down to this: Wallis accepted the concept of mathematical indivisibles; Hobbes (and Sorbière with him) did not. Therein lay the difference.

Other books

Cousin Kate by Georgette Heyer
We Could Be Beautiful by Swan Huntley
El último Catón by Matilde Asensi
PacksBrokenHeart by Gwen Campbell
Intoxicating by Lori Wilde