The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics) (84 page)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
12.58Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

8
     We must go on to discuss how it is possible for action and passion to take place.
(25)

Some philosophers think that the ‘last’ agent—the ‘agent’ in the strictest sense—enters in through certain pores, and so the patient suffers action. It is in this way, they assert, that we see and hear and exercise all our other senses. Moreover, according to them, things are seen through air and water and other transparent bodies,
(30)
because such bodies possess pores, invisible indeed owing to their minuteness, but close-set and arranged in rows: and the more transparent the body, the more frequent and serial they suppose its pores to be.

Such was the theory which some philosophers (including Empedocles) advanced in regard to the structure of certain bodies. They do not restrict it to the bodies which act and suffer action: but ‘combination’ too, they say, takes place ‘only between bodies whose pores are in reciprocal symmetry’.
(35)
The most systematic and consistent theory, however, and one that applied to all bodies, was advanced by Leucippus and Democritus: and, in maintaining it, they took as their starting-point what naturally comes first.
[325a]

For some of the older philosophers
72
thought that ‘what is’ must of necessity be ‘one’ and immovable. The void, they argue,
(5)
‘is not’: but unless there is a void with a separate being of its own, ‘what is’ cannot be moved—nor again can it be ‘many’, since there is nothing to keep things apart. And in
this
respect,
73
they insist, the view
that the universe is not ‘continuous’ but ‘discretes-in-contact’
74
is no better than the view that there are ‘many’ (and not ‘one’) and a void.
75
For , if it is divisible through and through, there is no ‘one’, and therefore no ‘many’ either, but the Whole is void; while to maintain that it is divisible at some points,
(10)
but not at others, looks like an arbitrary fiction. For up to what limit is it divisible? And for what reason is part of the Whole indivisible, i. e. a
plenum
, and part divided? Further, they maintain, it is equally
76
necessary to deny the existence of motion.

Reasoning in this way, therefore, they were led to transcend sense-perception, and to disregard it on the ground that ‘one ought to follow the argument’: and so they assert that the universe is ‘one’ and immovable.
(15)
Some of them add that it is ‘infinite’, since the limit (if it had one) would be a limit against the void.

There were, then, certain thinkers who, for the reasons we have stated, enunciated views of this kind as their theory of ‘The Truth’.
77
 … Moreover, although these opinions appear to follow logically in a dialectical discussion, yet to believe them seems next door to madness when one considers the facts.
(20)
For indeed no lunatic seems to be so far out of his senses as to suppose that fire and ice are ‘one’: it is only between what
is
right, and what
seems
right from habit, that some people are mad enough to see no difference.

Leucippus, however, thought he had a theory which harmonized with sense-perception and would not abolish either coming-to-be and passing-away or motion and the multiplicity of things.
(25)
He made these concessions to the facts of perception: on the other hand, he conceded to the Monists that there could be no motion without a void. The result is a theory which he states as follows: ‘The void is a “not-being”, and no part of “what is” is a “not-being”; for what “is” in the strict sense of the term is an absolute
plenum
. This
plenum
,
(30)
however, is not “one”: on the contrary, it is a “many” infinite in number and invisible owing to the minuteness of their bulk. The “many” move in the void (for there is a void): and by coming together they produce “coming-to-be”, while by separating they produce “passing-away”. Moreover, they act and suffer action where-ever
they chance to be in contact (for
there
they are not “one”), and they generate by being put together and becoming intertwined. From the genuinely-one, on the other hand,
(35)
there never could have come-to-be a multiplicity, nor from the genuinely-many a “one”: that is impossible.
[325b]
But (just as Empedocles and some of the other philosophers say that things suffer action through their pores, so) all “alteration” and all “passion” take place in the way that has been explained: breaking-up (i. e. passing-away) is effected by means of the void, and so too is growth—solids creeping in to fill the void places.’
(5)

Empedocles too is practically bound to adopt the same theory as Leucippus. For he must say that there are certain solids which, however, are indivisible—unless there are continuous pores all through the body. But this last alternative is impossible: for
then
there will be nothing solid in the body (nothing beside the pores) but all of it will be void. It is necessary, therefore, for his ‘contiguous discretes’ to be indivisible, while the intervals between them—which he calls ‘pores’—must be void.
(10)
But this is precisely Leucippus’s theory of action and passion.

Such, approximately, are the current explanations of the manner in which some things ‘act’ while others ‘suffer action’. And as regards the Atomists, it is not only clear what their explanation is: it is also obvious that it follows with tolerable consistency from the assumptions they employ.
(15)
But there is less obvious consistency in the explanation offered by the other thinkers. It is not clear, for instance, how, on the theory of Empedocles, there is to be ‘passing-away’ as well as ‘alteration’. For the primary bodies of the Atomists—the primary constituents of which bodies are composed, and the ultimate elements into which they are dissolved—are indivisible, differing from one another only in figure. In the philosophy of Empedocles, on the other hand, it is evident that all the other bodies down to the ‘elements’ have their coming-to-be and their passing-away: but it is not clear how the ‘elements’ themselves,
(20)
severally in their aggregated masses, come-to-be and pass-away. Nor is it possible for Empedocles to explain how they do so, since he does not assert that Fire too
78
(and similarly every one of his other ‘elements’) possesses ‘elementary constituents’ of itself.

Such an assertion would commit him to doctrines like those which Plato has set forth in the
Timaeus
.
79
For although both Plato and Leucippus postulate elementary constituents that are indivisible and distinctively characterized by figures,
(25)
there is this great difference between
the two theories: the ‘indivisibles’ of Leucippus (i) are solids, while those of Plato are planes, and (ii) are characterized by an infinite variety of figures, while the characterizing figures employed by Plato are limited in number.
(30)
Thus the ‘comings-to-be’ and the ‘dissociations’ result from the ‘indivisibles’ (
a) according to Leucippus
through the void and through contact (for it is at the point of contact that each of the composite bodies is divisible), but (
b) according to Plato
in virtue of contact alone, since he denies there is a void.

Now we have discussed ‘indivisible planes’ in the preceding treatise.
80
(35)
But with regard to the assumption of ‘indivisible solids’, although we must not now enter upon a detailed study of its consequences, the following criticisms fall within the compass of a short digression:—

(I) The Atomists are committed to the view that every ‘indivisible’ is incapable alike of receiving a sensible property (for nothing can ‘suffer action’ except through the void) and of producing one—no ‘indivisible’ can be, e. g., either hard or cold.
[326a]
Yet it is surely a paradox that an exception is made of ‘the hot’—‘the hot’ being assigned as peculiar to the spherical figure: for,
(5)
that being so, its ‘contrary’ also (‘the cold’) is bound to belong to another of the figures. If, however, these properties (heat and cold) do belong to the ‘indivisibles’, it is a further paradox that they should not possess heaviness and lightness,
(10)
and hardness and softness. And yet Democritus says ‘the more any indivisible exceeds, the heavier it is’—to which we must clearly add ‘and the hotter it is’. But if
that
is their character, it is impossible they should not be affected by one another: the ‘slightly-hot indivisible’, e. g., will inevitably suffer action from one which far exceeds it in heat. Again, if any ‘indivisible’ is ‘hard’, there must also be one which is ‘soft’: but ‘the soft’ derives its very name from the fact that it suffers a certain action—for ‘soft’ is that which yields to pressure. (II) But further, not only is it paradoxical (i) that no property except figure should belong to the ‘indivisibles’: it is also paradoxical (ii) that,
(15)
if other properties do belong to them, one only of these additional properties should attach to each—e. g. that
this
‘indivisible’ should be cold and
that
‘indivisible’ hot. For, on that supposition, their substance would not even be uniform.
81
And it is equally impossible (iii) that more than one of these additional properties should belong to the single ‘indivisible’. For, being
indivisible
, it will possess
these properties in the same point
82
—so that, if it ‘suffers action’ by being chilled, it will also,
qua
chilled, ‘act’ or ‘suffer action’ in some other way.
(20)
And the same line of argument applies to all the other properties too: for the difficulty we have just raised confronts, as a necessary consequence, all who advocate ‘indivisibles’ (whether solids or planes), since their ‘indivisibles’ cannot become either ‘rarer’ or ‘denser’ inasmuch as there is no void in them. (III) It is a further paradox that there should be small ‘indivisibles’, but not large ones.
(25)
For it is natural enough, from the ordinary point of view, that the larger bodies should be more liable to fracture than the small ones, since they (viz. the large bodies) are easily broken up because they collide with many other bodies. But why should indivisibility
as such
be the property of small, rather than of large, bodies? (IV) Again, is the substance of all those solids uniform, or do they fall into sets which differ from one another—as if,
(30)
e. g., some of them, in their aggregated bulk, were ‘fiery’, others ‘earthy’? For (i) if all of them are uniform in substance, what is it that separated one from another? Or why, when they come into contact, do they not coalesce into one, as drops of water run together when drop touches drop (for the two cases are precisely parallel)? On the other hand (ii) if they fall into differing sets, how are these characterized? It is clear, too,
(35)
that
these
,
83
rather than the ‘figures’, ought to be postulated as ‘original reals’, i. e. causes from which the phenomena result.
[326b]
Moreover, if they differed in substance, they would both act and suffer action on coming into reciprocal contact. (V) Again, what is it which sets them moving? For if their ‘mover’ is other than themselves, they are such as to ‘suffer action’. If, on the other hand, each of them sets itself in motion, either (
a
) it will be divisible (‘imparting motion’
qua this
, ‘being moved’
qua that
),
(5)
or (
b
) contrary properties will attach to it in the same respect—i. e. ‘matter’ will be identical-in-potentiality as well as numerically-identical.
84

As to the thinkers who explain modification of property through the movement facilitated by the pores, if this is supposed to occur notwithstanding the fact that the pores are filled, their postulate of pores is superfluous. For if the whole body suffers action under these conditions, it would suffer action in the same way even if it had no pores but were just its own continuous self.
(10)
Moreover, how can their account of ‘vision through a
medium
’ be correct? It is impossible
for to penetrate the transparent bodies at their ‘contacts’; and impossible for it to pass through their pores if every pore be full. For how will that
85
differ from having no pores at all? The body will be uniformly ‘full’ throughout.
(15)
But, further, even if these passages, though they must
contain
bodies, are ‘void’, the same consequence will follow once more.
86
And if they are ‘too minute to admit any body’, it is absurd to suppose there is a ‘minute’ void and yet to deny the existence of a ‘big’ one (no matter how small the ‘big’ may be
87
), or to imagine ‘the void’ means anything else than a body’s place—whence it clearly follows that to every body there will correspond a void of equal cubic capacity.
(20)

As a general criticism we must urge that to postulate pores is superfluous. For if the agent produces no effect by touching the patient, neither will it produce any by passing through its pores. On the other hand, if it acts by contact, then—even without pores—some things will ‘suffer action’ and others will ‘act’, provided they are by nature adapted for reciprocal action and passion.
(25)
Our arguments have shown that it is either false or futile to advocate pores in the sense in which some thinkers conceive them. But since bodies are divisible through and through, the postulate of pores is ridiculous: for,
qua
divisible, a body can fall into separate parts.

9
     Let us explain the way in which things in fact possess the power of generating,
(30)
and of acting and suffering action: and let us start from the principle we have often enunciated. For, assuming the distinction between (
a
) that which is
potentially
and (
b
) that which is
actually
such-and-such, it is the nature of the first, precisely in so far as it is what it is, to suffer action
through and through
, not merely to be susceptible in some parts while insusceptible in others. But its susceptibility varies in degree, according as it is more or less such-and-such, and one would be more justified in speaking of ‘pores’ in this connexion
88
: for instance,
(35)
in the metals there are veins of ‘the susceptible’ stretching continuously through the substance.
[327a]

So long, indeed, as any body is naturally coherent and one, it is
insusceptible. So, too, bodies are insusceptible so long as they are not in contact either with one another or with other bodies which are by nature such as to act and suffer action. (To illustrate my meaning: Fire heats not only when in contact, but also from a distance. For the fire heats the air, and the air—being by nature such as both to act and suffer action—heats the body.
(5)
) But the supposition that a body is ‘susceptible in some parts, but insusceptible in others’ the following account results from the distinctions we established at the beginning.
89
For (i) if magnitudes are not divisible through and through—if, on the contrary, there are indivisible solids or planes—then indeed no body would be susceptible through and through: but neither would any be continuous. Since, however, (ii) this is false, i. e. since every body is divisible,
(10)
there is no difference between ‘having been divided into parts which remain in contact’ and ‘being divisible’. For if a body ‘
can
be separated at the contacts’ (as some thinkers express it), then, even though it has not yet been divided, it will be in a state of dividedness—since, as it
can
be divided, nothing inconceivable results.
90
And (iii) the supposition is open to this general objection—it is a paradox that ‘passion’ should occur in this manner
only
,
(15)
viz. by the bodies being split. For this theory abolishes ‘alteration’: but we see the same body
liquid
at one time and
solid
at another, without losing its continuity. It has suffered this change not by ‘division’ and ‘composition’, nor yet by ‘turning’ and ‘intercontact’ as Democritus asserts; for it has passed from the liquid to the solid state without any change of ‘grouping’ or ‘position’ in the constituents of its substance.
(20)
Nor are there contained within it those ‘hard’ (i. e. congealed) particles ‘indivisible in their bulk’: on the contrary, it is liquid—and again, solid and congealed—uniformly all through. This theory, it must be added, makes growth and diminution impossible also. For if there is to be
apposition
(instead of the growing thing having changed as a whole, either by the admixture of something or by its own transformation),
(25)
increase of size will not have resulted in any and every part.

So much, then, to establish that things generate and are generated, act and suffer action, reciprocally; and to distinguish the way in which these processes
can
occur from the (impossible) way in which some thinkers say they occur.

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
12.58Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Executive Treason by Grossman, Gary H.
Chilling Effect by Unknown
The Drowned Vault by N. D. Wilson
Save My Soul by Elley Arden
The Manual of Darkness by Enrique de Heriz
Scraps of Paper by Griffith, Kathryn Meyer
My Secret Unicorn by Linda Chapman
Toast Mortem by Bishop, Claudia
Needle by Goodman, Craig