Read The Blackwell Companion to Sociology Online
Authors: Judith R Blau
crises? Many postmodernists, reflecting on the contemporary global economy,
contend that hyper-industrialized societies that have moved beyond historicity
can only experience chaos or make adjustments to limited, controlled change.
Clearly, this pessimistic view is shortsighted and ignores the human capacity for reflection and for possessing an historical awareness. I take the view that societal movements emerge in all types of societies, and, in particular, they emerge in
those endowed with historicity ± capable of cognitively, economically, and
morally investing in themselves. For that reason, contemporary neoliberalism,
even on a near global scale, does not preclude societal movements.
Societal Movements and Democracy
One of the reasons why I have analyzed societal movements for such a long time
is that I felt it necessary to radically and intellectually criticize revolutionary actions and ideologies, which, from the Reign of Terror to Leninism, have
always resulted in essentially totalitarian governments or even in fascism. My
central thesis is that we cannot separate the forming of social actors and, therefore, of societal movements from the autonomy of the issues underlying their
actions ± hence from the political mediation that constitute democracy's central, indispensable element. The Subject, societal movements, and democracy are as
The Subject and Societal Movements
443
inseparable as historical necessity, revolutionary action, and totalitarianism,
which represent their darker side. Societal movements, of whatever sort, bear
them within democratic aspirations. They seek to give a voice to those who have
no voice and bring them into political and economic decision-making. In con-
trast, revolutionary actors dream of cultural, ethnic, political, or social purification, of a unified and transparent society, of creating a new mankind, and of
eradicating whatever counters a unanimity that soon has no other reason for
being than to organize political support for a totalitarian power.
This general conception leads us, as sociologists, to maintain that the presence of a societal movement is linked neither to a revolutionary situation nor to the force of an ideological discourse or line of politics. Rather, it is linked to
the actor's capacity for working out a praxis ± to a commitment to societal
conflict and the defense of societal values, i.e. values that cannot be reduced to interests and, consequently, that cannot lead to the annihilation of one's
opponent. A movement's meaning lies neither in the situation where the move-
ment forms nor in the consciousness that ideologists ascribe to it or impose on it.
The meaning is in its ability to undertake a certain type of action and place social conflict and issues on a certain level. In opposition to an `èconomicist'' tradition often linked to Marxism, I have constantly defended the idea of a societal
movement and a historical actor. In my first study of the working-class move-
ment (Touraine, 1965), I stated that this movement was defending workers'
autonomy. We would be caricaturing the study of the consciousness of social
movements were we to reduce it to its most ideological forms. In effect, the latter often lie the furthest from praxis; and when they do not, the movement has, in
fact, turned into an authoritarian or totalitarian anti-movement. All forms of
absolute ideological mobilization ± the identification of a social actor with God, Reason, History or the Nation ± entail the destruction of societal movements.
The latter are open to conflict, debate, and democracy, whereas ideological
movements risk replacing plurality with unanimity, conflict with homogeneity,
and participation with manipulation. Revolutionary intellectuals and leaders,
demagogues and fundamentalists, are the active agents in the destruction of
social movements. How can this escape our notice at the end of a century
teeming with neo-communitarian movements, the most powerful of which call
for a theocratic society?
Nowadays, given the globalization of the economy, we see arising, on the one
hand, societal movements for minority rights, immigrant rights, and, more
generally, human rights, but we are also witnessing anti-movements, which are
giving birth to sects and cults in democratic lands and to new totalitarian
movements on a national, ethnic, or religious basis. Here I am using a notion
that many commentators ± without giving it much thought ± have avoided
because they wish to ignore the difficulties of comparing the Nazi and commun-
ist systems with contemporary nationalist and religious fundamentalist move-
ments. Is it so hard to admit that each totalitarian system, despite its specific aspects, belongs to a general type? Recourse to à`faith,'' whether Islam, Christianity, or Hinduism, leads to religious warfare, which communism and the
revolutionary Mexican system, despite their violently anti-religious campaigns,
444
Alain Touraine
avoided. Beyond the specific aspects of each totalitarian system, all of them share one characteristic, namely an absolute political power that speaks in the name of a people (a particular historical, national, or cultural group) and an assertion of absolute superiority (as being representative of a reality above politics and the economy). A totalitarian system is always popular, national, and doctrinaire. It subordinates social practices to a power that claims to incarnate the idea that a people represent and defends a faith, race, class, history, or territory.
Obviously, totalitarianism destroys democracy, but it also annihilates social,
cultural, and historical movements and actors. It reduces historicity by using
economic or cultural resources for constructing a closed mythical identity, itself reduced in practice to the justification of an absolute power. The idea of a people has always been a disguise for an absolutist state. It is no accident that the
totalitarian, then authoritarian, governments in the communist countries
dependent on the Soviet Union chose to call themselves ``people's republics.''
Totalitarianism is the central problem of the twentieth century. In like manner, when political activists reject elections or bring excessive moral or material
pressure to bear on those who do not share their point of view, they destroy
the social movement for which they claim to be speaking. They act like dema-
gogues (or Red Guards) rather than like the vanguard leading a class, nation or
socioeconomic category. In short, a societal movement is praxis and not just a
consciousness, and is fully linked to the affirmation that there is no societal
movement without democracy, and vice versa.
Social Movements in a Non-democratic Situation
Situation
An objection immediately comes to mind. Does this vision not focus solely on
developed lands, where modernization is self-sustaining? Does it not overlook
situations where democracy does not exist, because of the arbitrary power
imposed by a national or foreign state or an oligarchy interested in speculation and social power more than in economic rationality? This is such an important
objection that the answers to it serve to guide the analysis of social movements.
It calls for two complementary answers.
The first answer is that there can be no development without popular societal
movements and democracy. Development results from combining three major
factors: the abundance and quality of investment; the distribution of the fruits of growth; and public consciousness of the political unit. In effect, nation and
modernization cannot be separated, since a developed economy is a dense,
coherent, convergent network of exchanges, transactions, and interactions
among all societal sectors. More simply, development supposes a ruling elite
accumulating resources and making long-term decisions; but it also requires
redistributive and leveling forces, universal participation in the process of modernization, and the reduction of social and cultural privileges. These forces, born out of popular mobilization, have recourse to political institutions. Instead of saying, as many do, that development is a condition for democracy, I contend
that democracy is a condition for development. The inability of the Soviet Union The Subject and Societal Movements
445
to really develop and its increasing paralysis provided evidence in support of
this. But is the fast growth of China and of other lands in Asia, or elsewhere, not counter-evidence? We must answer no. In China, we observe the breakup of a
totalitarian system and, in the coastal provinces, the rapid growth of a market
economy under the leadership of decision-making centers located abroad. This
breakup has positive effects, especially coming as it does after the Cultural
Revolution's destructive violence. But if social movements do not form, if
democracy is not born, the historical process under way in China will disinteg-
rate into a new authoritarianism or else into chaos. The Soviet Union's former
satellites and former Yugoslavia, too, are looking for a way between democratic
development and regression into authoritarianism. Such regression has had
tragic consequences in Serbia and has negatively affected Romania and several
other ex-Soviet countries. Meanwhile, the communists' comeback in Poland,
Hungary, Bulgaria, and Lithuania, and their success in elections in Russia and
elsewhere, cannot ± at present ± be interpreted as a defeat for democracy and
modernization.
Self-sustaining growth is a worthy objective, but this conception must be
broadened to take into account other factors. When the dominant mode of
development is of a domestic sort, there is a risk that authoritarian agencies
will attempt to control the people or reduce them to mere resources. And when
the dominant mode of development is of a market sort, social movements
inevitably disintegrate into a multitude of pressure groups whose demands
make social inequality worse. Can social movements exist in non-democratic
situations? Let us push these questions even further. Are there democratic
elements, hence movements, whose actions tend toward a despotic or market
model instead of a democratic one?
This second answer takes us back to the analysis of the Subject, which can
assert itself only through struggling against both the marketplace and commodi-
fied community. This means that the Subject arises as a form of opposition and
liberation within the world of the marketplace and within the universe of the
community. Indeed, societal movements, like the Subject itself, arise within a
mode of development or even in forms of social power.
The major historical case is that of collective movements in authoritarian
societies ruled by a despotic power, a national oligarchy, or a foreign colonial power. In this case, movements are forced to combine the defense of the
oppressed and the demands for democracy with a revolutionary action for
destroying the powers that be. Even in democratic lands, the working-class
movement has always borne its share of violence in reaction to the violence of
employers or governments. The strategy of a collective movement and of its
leaders consists in combining actions for breaking with the existing order with
democratic actions ± thè`logic'' of the struggle against the powers that be with actions for defending freedom and, thus, political consciousness. This combination often fails. For instance, the labor movement has sometimes been an
instrument, lacking autonomy, in the service of a new political power; and,
sometimes, it has only defended relatively privileged socioeconomic categories.
But these failures, however many times they have happened, must not keep us
446
Alain Touraine
from realizing that a cultural, historical, or societal movement was present,
despite the non-democratic outcome. True, the Algerian national movement
has led to a military dictatorship that quells popular opposition. Nonetheless,
it was an anti-colonial movement for national liberation. Nor does the horror of the Reign of Terror detract from the events of June 1789 that introduced
democracy in France. A movement is never purely democratic, nor does a
revolution ever entirely lack democratic contents.
Despair or Hope?
We would weaken the idea of a societal movement were we to reduce it to
naming a particular ± more ideal than real ± type of collective action. It is a
concept or theoretical formulation. The idea of a societal movement (and, more
broadly, of a social movement) forces us to give up the too easy quests of
conservative thought, which looks for factors of integration, and of revolution-
ary thought, which denounces a system of domination as incapable of being
either restrained or reformed.
This idea also protects us against the fragmentation that menaces collective
action and, indeed, all aspects of social life. On the one hand, social movements seem to be less focused on being interest groups currently than on efforts for
defending social integration from ``social fractures'' and ruptures of social bonds.
The theme of exclusion, which has replaced exploitation, contains this idea. On
the other hand, `ìdentity movements'' are abounding, in the United States where
women, homosexuals, African Americans, and ethnic or national communities
are asserting cultural autonomy while also fighting against discrimination, but