Let us take the earliest exhibition first. The Glories of the Past show, held at the Metropolitan Museum in New York in 1990, was the title given to an exhibition based on the Shelby White and Leon Levy Collection. Chippindale and Gill found that only 4 percent of this collection had any known provenance. Ninety percent had no provenance whatsoever, and the remaining 6 percent fell into the notorious “said to be” or “probably” categories.
The Crossroads of Asia exhibition at the Fitzwilliam Museum, Cambridge, in 1992, included a collection belonging to a mysterious organization, “A.I.C.,” which was never explained but is thought to have been linked to Mr. Neil Kreitman of California, who certainly owned one of the more important objects in the collection in the early 1980s and who took part in the preparation of the show. In this collection, 88 percent of the objects had no history before the exhibition but were legitimized, say Chippindale and Gill, because the Fitzwilliam show also featured artifacts from the British Museum, the Ashmolean, and the Louvre in Paris.
And in the George Ortiz Collection exhibition, In Pursuit of the Absolute, shown at the Royal Academy in London in 1994, 23 percent had no provenance at all, with a further 62 percent made up of “said to be's,” “possibly's,” and “allegedly's.” That left just 15 percent with some sort of provenance, however euphemistic.
The point here is not that there were one or two objects in each of these
collections that were illicit but that the vast majority were. They had surfaced recently and had no secure provenance. And in none of these usually prestigious institutions did the scholars turn a hair.
Another aspect of the trade that Chippindale and Gill highlight is the close link between illegally excavated and smuggled goods, on the one hand, and widespread faking, on the other. According to the thermoluminescence laboratory in Oxford, some 40 percent of antiquities sent in for testing “are found to be of modern manufacture.” (Fake Cycladic statues can be expertly aged, the story goes, by wrapping in cooked spaghetti.)
In the first place, few collectors appear willing to acknowledge even the possibility that some of the objects in their possession are fake. Much more important, however, is the fact that several unusual categories of Cycladic antiquities are known only from unprovenanced objects. Since it is very difficult to tell forged and real Cycladic figures apart (because the available scientific tests don't work with stone), it is entirely possible that whole areas of this field are forged.
Intellectually, this is a very serious problem. To begin with, in the early years when Cycladic figures became fashionable to collect, all of them were about the length of a forearm. After they became popular in the salesrooms, however, bigger statues began to turn up on the marketâwhich fetched higher prices. But because only two of these have a secure provenance and both were discovered before 1900 (now in the National Museum in Athens), and because science can't tell the fake from the real thing, how can we be sure that
any
of these more recently acquired larger and more expensive statues are real? The answer is: We cannot. The same argument applies to male figures. Where Cycladic figures can be gendered, they are femaleâno male figure has ever been found with a secure provenance. So once again the
entire category
of male Cycladic figures may be fake.
The high proportion of unprovenanced and recently surfaced antiquities
in a collection is one measure of the damage done by the commercially minded salesrooms and unthinking collectors. But Chippindale and Gill are more sophisticated than that. They have studied the unprovenanced objects that have been offered for sale, and acquired by modern collectors, and they have identified at least five ways in which the archaeological contexts of these artifacts are “lost.” Taken together, these five forms of loss amount to a powerful indictment of collecting. For without an adequate grounding in knowledge, such collections have no point and may do more harm than good.
One form of loss has already been referred toâthat the wide spread of unprovenanced antiquities, allied to the massive jumble of fakes, means that whole categories of object may be spurious. That apart, potentially the most damaging loss to archaeology is the large number of objects that are, or are supposed to be, found in groups. Chippindale and Gill give endless examples of this, but again, two will suffice.
For example, in the George Ortiz Collection, two Corinthian terracottas, a hare and a comast (a dancer), are “said to have been found in the same tomb,” allegedly in Etruria. In secure circumstances, this might tell us something about the tomb, or the person buried there. The find spot might help explain the juxtaposition of hare and comast, which on the face of it is not at all an obvious pairing and may have an unusual meaning. But without such knowledge, the whole exercise is futile. In another case, two bronze statuettes of Heracles in the Crossroads of Asia collection shown at the Fitzwilliam Museum in Cambridge are said to have been found together in Afghanistan. They are more valuable if they have been found together, because this is rare. But who can tell if it is true, and in any case what was the significance of two Heracleses being found together? We may never know. There are many examples in auction catalogs of objects said to be found together, but who can prove this? We only have the salesroom's word to go on, and behind them dealers and looters with a commercial interest in these things being found together, so that they fetch more.
The sheer futility of all this is underlined by yet another phenomenon identified by Chippindale and Gill, which they term “wish fulfilment.” They give three telling examples in this category. The first is a marble “egg” in the Ortiz Collection that, allegedly, comes from the Cyclades.
A date for this is given as 3200â2100 BC. But without any knowledge of its provenance, or the context in which it was found, this object is actually no more than an egg-shaped pebble that may have been picked up on any of the Greek islands. To call it an “egg,” thereby implying intention on the part of the artist and a role for the object, perhaps, in religious practices, is entirely unwarranted, archaeologically speaking. It is no more than a collector's conceit.
Similarly, the Ortiz Collection also contains several clay three-legged chairs that are described as “thrones”âthe basis for this being that the objects are Mycenaean and Mycenaeans are known to have constructed objects “that accompanied the deceased to their tombs.” But without the context, who is to say they are Mycenaean in the first place and who is to say they are not something entirely differentâmilking stools, for example? Here again, the wishes of the collector may have taken over from disinterested scholarship.
A third common effect of wish fulfillment is to see all clay and marble figures as “idols,” interesting statuettes that played a part in mysterious cults. Usually we do not know that: They may just as easily have been toysâ“less interesting,” and therefore less valuable. In addition, the very word “idol” is an interpretation; we have no idea whether the figure represents a deity or the deceased, or served some other function. “Idol” is really a vague descriptive term, and no more should be read into it.
In these varied ways, scholarship is devalued and the wishes of the collectorâwhich may have no basis in factâtake precedence over the work of disinterested and better-informed scholars. Bluntly, these may be considered forms of intellectual corruption.
But far and away the best example of the way our understanding of the past has been distorted by the values of the auction houses and by the activities of rich and not-very-knowledgeable collectors (who nonetheless often like to pose as scholars) is the whole concept of Cycladic figures. Already plagued by fakes and copies, the collecting and salesroom framework of “art” is being imposed on an archaeology that may simply have no relation whatsoever to that structure.
The most ludicrous and revealing example of this is the practice, now widespread, of attributing this or that Cycladic figure to this or that “Master.” Already we have, for example, sculptures alleged to be by the
“Doumas Master,” the “Berlin Master,” the “Fitzwilliam Master,” and the “Copenhagen Master.” In one of Christie's catalogs there is even a reference to a statue as being “in the style of the Schuster Master.” Yet “Master” is a concept that was invented to cope with Renaissance art and in so doing contains two important ingredients that simply do not apply to Cycladic art and many other types of antiquities. First, it impliesâas was true of the Renaissanceâthat there
were
masters, artists capable of producing masterpieces in their own distinctive style and good enough to be followed by other, lesser artists. Second, as traditionally used, the qualification of the master was confined to something distinctive about his style when his name wasn't known. As referred to earlier, it was based on the ideas of the Italian connoisseur, Giovanni Morrelli, taken up and developed by Bernard Berenson, who argued that authorship in an unsigned work could be identified by little, unconscious flourishesâthe way the drapery was painted, for example, or the treatment of the ears. Thus, in painting we have the “Master of S. Bartholomew,” named from a series of panels in Cologne and Munich and where the style suggests the painter was from Utrecht, or the “Master of the Aix Annunciation,” named for a triptych now in three placesâAix, Amsterdam, and Rotterdamâin which the style suggests a Flemish artist.
In the case of Cycladic art, however, this academic tradition is corrupted. In the first place, the “Masters” are named not after the defining characteristic of the artist, which sets his work apart, or after an important work by him, which epitomizes his particular skillsâinstead, they are named after the owner of the object, the collection of which it forms a part, or the museum where the collection is held, the aim being either a commercial one (to suggest how good the sculptor was) or to flatter the owner. Once again, scholarly aims have been corrupted by commercialism. This is not to deny that study of the artistic variations between Cycladic figures is not possible or desirable, or that there are “subgroups” among them, just that the concept of “Master,” given the evidence we have (or rather don't have), is intellectually meaningless.
Nor does it make sense, again on the available evidence, to speak of regional styles of Cycladic art, according to the islands (Naxos, Paros, Ios, and so on), since most of the provenances attributing objects to these islands are so flimsy as to be meaningless.
Some statues are said to have “canonical” proportions, presuming Cycladic artists had such a canon in mind, and others are described as “postcanonical,” implying a development over time. Again, these ideas are based as much on unprovenancedâand therefore possibly fakeâmaterial as on objects that are “archaeologically secure.” They imply an understanding of mathematics, in order to achieve these complex canonical proportions, for which there is as yet little evidence. Under the circumstances, any concept of a “canon,” or implication of development, is premature, though that might change if more hard evidence about the circumstances of excavation became available.
On top of it all, some of the figures have been discovered with traces of blue or red paint on them, so that we are not even sure what color they originally were and how they were decorated. In such circumstances, how on earth can we judge who was a master and who was not? We do not even know if the current fashion for displaying Cycladic figuresâin museums as well as in auction catalogsâin an upright vertical position is correct. They are decorated with elaborate toes pointing downâwhich suggests the toes were designed to be seen, but this means that the figures could never have stood by themselves. Probably, they should be displayed horizontally, not vertically.
In amassing and collating such detailed evidence, Chippindale and Gill have taken archaeologists' arguments about the damage done by looters much further than they have ever gone before. In particular, and without letting the salesrooms off the hook, they have brought collectors and museums under the spotlight, putting them on notice that their actions are no less to blame than are those of the looters themselves in causing so much damage to our understanding of the past. Collectors such as George Ortiz have often argued that even if their collections contain loot, then at least those objects are better looked after in collections like his and are available for study. Chippindale and Gill expose that for the nonsense it is. In theory, they say, the objects may be available to study; in practice, there is little that can be done when the most interesting aspects of the objects have been lostâin the looting.