Authors: Russell Shorto
These battlesâbetween Cartesians and the church, between Cartesians and state power, and among the Cartesians themselvesâraged through the dying days of the seventeenth century and into the eighteenth. There would be casualties among the Cartesians. People would be excommunicated and forced into exile. Rohault himself would be accused of heresy and banned from holding public lectures.
More importantly, other thinkersâthe German Gottfried Leibniz, the Amsterdam Jew Baruch Spinozaâwould spin Cartesianism in new directions, broadening the scope of philosophical inquiry. Beyond the level of philosophy, the roots of Cartesianismâespecially “the method” and Descartes' mind-body dualismâwould penetrate all aspects of culture, steadily bringing a new world into being, transforming views about everything from sex to education to the role of women to the relationship between humans and their environment, giving this first modern philosophy fresh life while at the same time pushing its founder farther into the recesses of the past.
Unholy Relics
OR A CENTURY AFTER THEIR SECOND BURIAL, IN
Paris, Descartes' bones rested undisturbed. But while they moldered and the church of Ste.-Geneviève, in which they were entombed, quietly crumbled into ruin (as it lost its long battles against both the French crown and the neighboring church of St.-Etienne, with which it shared a wall and ancient territorial rivalries), the world of the living transformed itself in unheard-of ways. If someone from any of the previous centuries could have revisited earth in the 1700s, it might reasonably have seemed that human beings had become drunk on invention. Nitrogen was discovered, electricity harnessed, the first appendectomy performed. The income tax came into being. The Hawaiian islands were discovered. The fountain pen was invented, and the fire extinguisher, the piano, the tuning fork, and the flush toilet. Clocks, microscopes, compasses, lamps, and carriages were refined. In the English city of Birmingham alone, the small group of men who called themselves the Lunar Society, epitomizing the passion for combining invention and industry, discovered oxygen, created the steam engine, identified digitalis as a treatment for heart ailments, and built the world's first factories. Men caught in the grip of a mania for collecting and classifying roamed the earth and gathered spiders, minerals, fossils, and flowers. Museums, dictionaries, and encyclopedias came into existence. SurnamesâWatt, Fahrenheit, Schweppe, Celsius, Wedgwoodâbecame products or terminology.
To state the above is to state the obvious: the Enlightenment and the Scientific Revolution are part of every school curriculum. What is perhaps less obvious is how threads from these events ran backward in time. We are used to thinking of the Enlightenment as an eighteenth-century phenomenon, in which intellectuals urged changes across society based on a commitment to reason. But recently historians have cleared paths back through the previous century, revealing how networks of events and personalitiesâinventors and the rippling consequences of their inventions, explorers who wielded sails, microscopes or quill pensârooted the ideas of Jefferson and Rousseau in the program of Descartes.
The link between Descartes and the ensuing decades of invention and discovery is not so apparent; less still is the link between Descartes and our own era of invention and discovery. Cartesianism isn't exactly in the air these days. There are no university degrees in it. You don't run into parents who say they want their children to grow up to be Cartesians. We tend to prefer “science” when we're talking about a particular systematic way of exploring the natural world.
Scienceâ
the word itself, coming from the Latin for knowledgeâhas been around since the Middle Ages, when it meant something like art or discipline, as in the science of war or the science of horsemanship. Its use in the sense that we mean today didn't get fixed until around 1800. Meanwhile, “Cartesianism” faded away in the early 1700s.
What happened to the Cartesians is one of the subplots of modernity. In a sense, they were engulfed by a great wave that swept over Europe in the late 1600s and early 1700s, which went by the name of Anglomania. The center of gravity of the “new philosophy” shifted from France to England. This was partly fad, but at its core was an appreciation of English practicality. The French approach to knowledgeâornate, rational, abstractâhad elegantly suited the medieval, Aristotelian edifice. Descartesâwith his grand system, his effort to construct a holistic view of reality based on reason and the cogito, which would encompass everything from salt crystals to God's grace, from human emotions to Jupiter's moonsâwas part of that. The British looked at the new thinking as more of a toolbox. They tinkered; they came up with improved metal alloys and ceramic glazes and watch springs. If the French created a new philosophy, the English invented applied science. While the French developed their salons into ornate social institutions, English craftsmen employed apprentices and made them sign hard-nosed contracts such as the one in which young Josiah Wedgwood promised that “at Cards Dice or any other unlawful Games he shall not Play, Taverns or Ale Houses he shall not haunt or frequent, Fornication he shall not commitâMatrimony he shall not Contract.”
There was a political dimension as well. Where the French state tried to control the new thinkingâin part by creating an academy of sciences that would officially bless or condemn proposed new avenues of studyâthe English were freelancers. They were thus more adept at innovation, so that inventors in Bristol or Birmingham, acting on their own initiative, raising capital and creating markets, became small-scale industrialists and began to reshape the way the world operated.
The individual most responsible for this changeâthe person who, it could be said, single handedly pushed Descartes into the pastâwas Isaac Newton. Newton's laws of motion, work in optics, and development of the principles of gravitation formed a hard, practical base on which the scientific revolution would be built. The French themselves lauded Newton as the herald of a new age. Voltaire, the godfather of the French Enlightenment, wrote of
“ la supériorité de la Philosophie anglaise”
and praised Newton as “the destroyer of the Cartesian system”âthat is, the man who brought science down out of the clouds of theory. This sort of nationalistic divide between thinking and doing crystallized in philosophy departments in the terms
rationalism
and
empiricism.
In this neat compartmentalization, Descartes is not only the father of modernity but the inventor of the “school” of rationalism, which perceives reality from a starting point in the human mind and whose leaders were all continental figures, and that of empiricism, whose main thinkersâJohn Locke, David Hume, and George Berkeley, English, Scottish, and Irish, respectivelyâbegan instead with the reality of the external world.
While there is truth in the shorthand, it is also misleading. Descartes' career, his lifelong focus on medicine and dissection and observation, belies the rationalist label. More to the point, he was foundational to
both
the rationalist and the empiricist traditions, as well as to the Enlightenment's political ideas. Beneath Newton's principles and Voltaire's maxims is the cogito. As a discipline, philosophy itself tends to forget this. As the present-day British philosopher Jonathan Rée puts it, Descartes “was the founder of the ânew philosophy,' whose work was carried on by Newton and later scientists. . . . The principles of the ânew philosophy,' and the theory of knowledge and the theory of human nature which go with it; the concepts of an idea, of mathematical laws of nature . . . are so fundamental to modern consciousness that it is hard not to regard them as part of the natural property of the human mind. But, in fact, they are a product of the seventeenth century, and above all the work of Descartes.”
Thus the essence of Cartesianismâits philosophical kernel, which encompassed much more than scienceânot only lived on but expanded into virtually every corner of human life, evolving and adapting and spawning new generations, each with its own characteristic traits but all of them linking back to their ancestor, even as the original Cartesians flickered into extinction.
“R
EASON VERSUS FAITH
” may be the chronic fever of modernity, but if the Western world caught it in the period of the Enlightenment the division was not as clear as some today might like to believe. There seems nowadays to be an ingrained notion that people of that era set reason firmly against faith and the two have ever since been locked in a death struggle. Maybe this idea comes from our desire to simplify things, our hunger for sound bites and text crawls. Maybe it gives clarity to both hard-core believers and the antireligion faction, both of which are very much alive today. People who want to drive society and politics via the motor of their religious viewsâwhether they are Muslims, American evangelicals, Roman Catholics, members of India's nationalist Hindu partyâhave been particularly vocal in recent years. But the other sideâpolitical atheists, you might call themâare voicing themselves, too, as evidenced by the titles of recent books:
The God Delusion, The End of Faith, God Is Not Great.
The root of these atheist manifestos is the belief that society woke up three or four centuries ago to the realization that God doesn't control the universe, that rather the blind forces of nature do, but that many people around the world are still caught in the trap of religion and are threatening, with violence and intimidation, to drag humanity down the drain. If the hard-core faithful have their ancient texts to rely on for foundations, the new atheists have the Enlightenment.
But the situation was never as simple as that. The fighting was more of a three-way affair, for the new philosophers were themselves split into two camps, each of which would have an enormous impact on modernity and each of which still exists, with representatives continuing their clashes on cable talk shows and in op-ed columns. The split began, as we have seen, with the first-generation Cartesians, with Malebranche et al. adapting the new philosophy to Catholic teaching while Rohault, Arnauld, and others kept the two apart. Over the next generations, the “moderates” continued to believe that reason would function alongside faith to increase human happiness and life span, end disease, reduce suffering of all kinds, and give people greater power over nature and greater freedom in their lives. These moderates worked with the church and within governments: many literally worked in either the church or the state apparatus. The moderate camp includes some of the most well-known figures of the Enlightenment: Montesquieu, Newton, Locke, Jefferson, Hobbes, Voltaire.
Then there was the other element. Two present-day historians of the periodâMargaret C. Jacob of UCLA and Jonathan Israel of the Institute for Advanced Study at Princetonâhave written nearly identically titled books giving a name to this more shadowy secularist camp. Jacob's
The Radical Enlightenment,
which appeared in 1981, and Israel's
Radical Enlightenment,
published in 2001, focus attention on thinkers of the period who looked to reason as a kind of new faith, who insisted that a necessary object of the thinking that followed from Descartes was to bring about the end of traditional religionâto end what they believed was the tyranny of superstition in which humanity had existed for millennia, a tyranny that, they argued, those in power, in church and state, had maintained for their own benefit. What's more, in many respects these early Enlightenment radicals didn't just pre-figure what was to come but fully developed the ideas that would lead to the world-historic changes of the later era. As Israel puts it, “It may be that the story of the High Enlightenment after 1750 is more familiar to readers and historians, but that does not alter the reality that the later movement was basically just one of consolidating, popularizing, and annotating revolutionary concepts introduced earlier.”
The changes taking place in the late 1600s and early 1700s weren't confined to gears and pulleys. Something more than mere inventiveness was involved. The idea of making reason the ground to thought and behavior had almost immediate consequences in the social sphere. As early as the 1660s, the Dutchman Franciscus van den Enden was advocating a radical new approach to society that included equal education for people of all classes, joint ownership of property, and democratically elected government. Van den Enden actually drew up a charter for a utopian community that would be based in the Dutch New World colony of New Netherland, with its capital of New Amsterdam on Manhattan Island. A group of settlers went so far as to establish a base for the community on Delaware Bay, but within months the English took over the Dutch colony (changing New Amsterdam to New York) and the schemeâperhaps the first attempt to enact a society based on the modern principle of democracyâended. In the 1720s, Alberto Radicatiâan Italian nobleman turned radical philosopherâsimilarly argued that natural philosophy showed that democracy was the only proper form of government. He also dismissed most biblical teaching and said that people should enjoy the pleasures of life but that, if life was really awful, suicide was reasonable. (As a true radical, he could only have been pleased when Italy's chief law officer called his principal work “the most impious and immoral book I have ever read.”)