289
This discussion assumes that the assumptions we previously made in discussing the entropy of our comoving patch remain valid—in particular, that it makes sense to think of the patch as an autonomous system. That is certainly not necessarily correct, but it is usually implicitly assumed by people who study these scenarios.
290
Aguirre and Gratton (2003). Hartle, Hawking, and Hertog (2008) also investigated universes with high entropy in the past and future and low entropy in the middle, in the context of Euclidean quantum gravity.
291
This is true even in ordinary nongravitational situations, where the total energy is strictly conserved. When a high-energy state decays into a lower-energy one, like a ball rolling down a hill, energy isn’t created or destroyed; it’s just transformed from a useful low-entropy form into a useless high-entropy form.
292
Farhi, Guth, and Guven (1990). See also Farhi and Guth (1987), and Fischler, Morgan, and Polchinski (1990a, 1990b). Guth writes about this work in his popular-level book (1997).
293
The most comprehensive recent work on this question was carried out by Anthony Aguirre and Matthew Johnson (2006). They catalogued all the different ways that baby universes might be created by quantum tunneling, but in the end were unable to make a definitive statement about what actually happens. (“The unfortunate bottom line, then, is that while the relation between the various nucleation processes is much clearer, the question of which ones actually occur remains open.”) From a completely different perspective, Freivogel et al. (2006) considered inflation in an anti-de Sitter background, using Maldacena’s correspondence. They concluded that baby universes were not created. But our interest is de Sitter backgrounds, not anti-de Sitter backgrounds; it’s unclear whether the results can be extended from one context to the other. For one more take on the evolution of de Sitter space, see Bousso (1998).
294
Carroll and Chen (2004).
295
One assumption here is that the de Sitter space is in a true vacuum state; in particular, that there is no other state of the theory where the vacuum energy vanishes, and spacetime could look like Minkowski space. To be honest, that is not necessarily a realistic assumption. In string theory, for example, we are pretty sure that 10-dimensional Minkowski space is a good solution of the theory. Unlike de Sitter, Minkowski space has zero temperature, so can plausibly avoid the creation of baby universes. To make the scenario described here work, we have to imagine either that there are no states with zero vacuum energy, or that the amount of spacetime that is actually in such a state is sufficiently small compared to the de Sitter regions.
16. EPILOGUE
296
And that’s despite the fact that, just as the manuscript was being completed, another book with exactly the same title appeared on the market! (Viola, 2009). His subtitle is quite different, however: “Rediscovering the Ageless Purpose of God.” I do hope nobody orders the wrong book by accident.
297
Feynman, Leighton, and Sands (1970), 46-8.
298
Popper (1959). Note that Popper went a bit further than the demarcation problem; he wanted to understand all of scientific progress as a series of falsified conjectures. Compared to how science is actually done, this is a fairly impoverished way of understanding the process; ruling out conjectures is important, but there’s a lot more that goes into the real workings of science.
299
See Deutsch (1997) for more on this point.
300
For one example among many, see Swinburne (2004).
301
Lemaître (1958).
302
Steven Weinberg put it more directly: “The more the universe seems comprehensible, the more it also seems pointless” (Weinberg 1977, 154).
303
I regret that this book has paid scant attention to current and upcoming new experiments in fundamental physics. The problem is that, as fascinating and important as those experiments are, it’s very hard to tell ahead of time what we are going to learn from them, especially about a subject as deep and all-encompassing as the arrow of time. We’re not going to build a telescope that will use tachyons to peer into other universes, unfortunately. What we might do is build particle accelerators that reveal something about supersymmetry, which in turn teaches us something about string theory, which we can use to understand more about quantum gravity. Or we might gather data from giant telescopes—collecting not only photons of light, but also cosmic rays, neutrinos, gravitational waves, or even particles of dark matter—that reveal something surprising about the evolution of the universe. The real world surprises us all the time: dark matter and dark energy are obvious examples. As a theoretical physicist, I’ve written this book from a rather theoretical perspective, but as a matter of history it’s often new experiments that end up awakening us from our dogmatic slumbers.
APPENDIX: MATH
304
These properties are behind the “magic of mathematics” appealed to above. For example, suppose we wanted to figure out what was meant by 10 to the power 0.5. I know that, whatever that number is, it has to have the property that 10
0.5
• 10
0.5
= 10
(0.5 + 0.5)
= 10
1
= 10.
In other words, the number 10
0.5
times itself gives us 10; that means that 10
0.5
must simply be the square root of 10. (And likewise for any other base raised to the power 0.5.) By similar tricks, we can figure out the exponential of any number we like.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Note: Many of these bibliography entries are referenced explicitly in the text, but many are not. Some were influential in shaping the point of view presented here; others were foils to be argued against. Some are research articles that fill in technical details on the topics of this book, while others provide additional background reading at an accessible level. All of them are interesting.
My favorite modern books about the arrow of time include David Albert’s
Time and Chance
, Huw Price’s
Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point
, Brian Greene’s
The Fabric of the Cosmos
, and Michael Lockwood’s
The Labyrinth of Time.
Any of those will give you a complementary viewpoint to that presented here. Etienne Klein’s
Chronos
, Craig Callender’s
Introducing Time
, and Paul Davies’s
About Time
all discuss the subject of time more broadly. For background in general relativity I suggest Kip Thorne’s
Black Holes and Time Warps
, and for black holes and information loss in particular Leonard Susskind’s
The Black Hole War
. For cosmology I recommend Dennis Overbye’s
Lonely Hearts of the Cosmos
or Alan Guth’s
The Inflationary Universe.
David Lindley’s
Boltzmann’s Atom
and Hans Christian von Baeyer’s
Warmth Disperses and Time Passes
provide fascinating historical background, as does Stephen Brush’s anthology of original papers on kinetic theory. Zeh’s
The Physical Basis of the Direction of Time
tackles the subject at a technical level.
Many of the modern (post-1992) research articles can be downloaded for free from the arXiv physics preprint server
http://arxiv.org/
.
More information and links to further resources can be found at the book’s Web site,
http://eternitytohere.com
.
Abbot, E. A.
Flatland: A Romance of Many Dimensions
. Cambridge: Perseus, 1899.
Adams, F., and Laughlin, G.
The Five Ages of the Universe: Inside the Physics of Eternity
. New York: Free Press, 1999.
Aguirre, A., and Gratton, S. “Inflation Without a Beginning: A Null Boundary Proposal.”
Physical Review D
67 (2003): 083515.
Aguirre, A., and Johnson, M. C. “Two Tunnels to Inflation.”
Physical Review D
73 (2006): 123529.
Alavi-Harati, A., et al. (KTeV Collaboration). “Observation of CP Violation in
KL
→ π
+
π-
e
+
e
-
Decays.”
Physical Review Letters
84 (2000): 408-11.
Albert, D. Z.
Quantum Mechanics and Experience.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992.
Albert, D. Z.
Time and Chance.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.
Albert, D. Z., and Loewer, B. “Interpreting the Many Worlds Interpretation.”
Synthese
77 (1988): 195-213.
Albrecht, A. “Cosmic Inflation and the Arrow of Time.” In
Science and Ultimate Reality: From Quantum to Cosmos
, edited by Barrow, J. D., Davies, P. C. W., and Harper, C. L. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Albrecht, A., and Sorbo, L. “Can the Universe Afford Inflation?”
Physical Review D
70 (2004): 63528.
Albrecht, A., and Steinhardt, P. J. “Cosmology for Grand Unified Theories with Radiatively Induced Symmetry Breaking.”
Physical Review Letters
48 (1982): 1220-23.
Ali, A., Ellis, J., and Randjbar-Daemi, S., eds.
Salamfestschrift: A Collection of Talks.
Singapore: World Scientific,. 1993.
Alpher, R. A., and Herman, R.
Genesis of the Big Bang
. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Amis, M.
Time’s Arrow
. New York: Vintage, 1991.
Angelopoulos, A., et al
.
(CPLEAR Collaboration). “First Direct Observation of Time Reversal Noninvari ance in the Neutral Kaon System.”
Physics Letters B
444 (1998): 43-51.
Arntzenius, F. “Time Reversal Operations, Representations of the Lorentz Group, and the Direction of Time.”
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B
35 (2004): 31-43.
Augustine, Saint.
Confessions
. Translated by H. Chadwick. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Avery, J.
Information Theory and Evolution
. Singapore: World Scientific, 2003.
Baker, N.
The Fermata.
New York: Random House, 2004.
Banks, T. “Entropy and Initial Conditions in Cosmology” (2007).
http://arxiv.org/abs/
hep-th/0701146.
Banks, T., and Fischler, W. “Holographic Cosmology 3.0.”
Physica Scripta
T117 (2005): 56-63.
Barbour, J.
The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics.
Oxford University Press, 1999.
Bardeen, J. M., Carter, B., and Hawking, S. W. “The Four Laws of Black Hole Mechanics.”
Communications in Mathematical Physics
31 (1973): 161-70.
Barrow, J. D., Davies, P. C. W., and Harper, C. L.
Science and Ultimate Reality: From Quantum to Cosmos
, honoring John Wheeler’s 90th birthday. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Barrow, J. D., and Tipler, F. J.
The Anthropic Cosmological Principle
. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988.
Baum, E. B.
What Is Thought?
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004.
Bekenstein, J. D. “Black Holes and Entropy.”
Physical Review D
7 (1973): 2333-46.
Bekenstein, J. D. “Statistical Black Hole Thermodynamics.”
Physical Review D
12 (1975): 3077-85.
Bennett, C. H. “Demons, Engines, and the Second Law.”
Scientific American
257, no. 5 (1987): 108-16.
Bennett, C. H., and Landauer, R. “Fundamental Limits of Computation.”
Scientific American
253, no. 1 (1985): 48-56.
Bojowald, M. “Loop Quantum Cosmology.”
Living Reviews in Relativity
8 (2006): 11.
Bojowald, M., and Tavakol, R. “Recollapsing Quantum Cosmologies and the Question of Entropy.”
Physical Review D
78 (2008): 23515.
Boltzmann, L. “Weitere Studien über das Wärmegleichgewicht unter Gasmoleculen” [Further studies on the thermal equilibrium of gas molecules].
Sitzungsberichte Akad. Wiss.
66 (1872): 275-370.
Boltzmann, L. “Über die Beziehung eines allgemeine mechanischen Satzes zum zweiten Hauptsatze der Warmetheorie” [On the relation of a general mechanical theorem to the Second Law of Thermodynamics].
Sitzungsberichte Akad. Wiss.
75 (1877): 67-73.
Boltzmann, L. “On Certain Questions of the Theory of Gases.”
Nature
51 (1895): 413-15.
Boltzmann, L. “Entgegnung auf die wärmetheoretischen Betrachtungen des Hern. E. Zermelo” [Reply to Zermelo’s remarks on the Theory of Heat].
Annalen der Physik
57 (1896): 773.
Boltzmann, L. “Zu Hrn. Zermelo’s Abhandlung ‘Über die mechanische Erklärung irreversibler Vorgänge’” [On Zermelo’s paper “On the Mechanical Explanation of Irreversible Processes”].
Annalen der Physik
60 (1897): 392.
Bondi, H., and Gold, T. “The Steady-State Theory of the Expanding Universe.”
Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society
108 (1948): 252-70.
Bostrom, N. “Are You Living in a Computer Simulation?”
Philosophical Quarterly
53 (2003): 243-55.