Men of Mathematics (111 page)

Read Men of Mathematics Online

Authors: E.T. Bell

BOOK: Men of Mathematics
7.38Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

A striking and important instance of the “existence” way of looking at the theory of sets is afforded by what is known as Zermelo's postulate (stated in 1904). “For every set
M
whose elements are sets
P
(that is,
M
is a set of
sets,
or a class of
classes),
the sets
P
being non-empty and non-overlapping (no two contain things in common), there exists at least one set
N
which contains precisely one
element from each of the sets
P
which constitute
M.”
Comparison of this with the previously stated definition of a set (or class) will show that the “we” men would not consider the postulate self-evident if the set
M
consisted, say, of an infinity of non-overlapping line segments. Yet the postulate seems reasonable enough. Attempts to prove it have failed. It is of considerable importance in all questions relating to continuity.

A word as to how this postulate came to be introduced into mathematics will suggest another of the unsolved problems of Cantor's theory. A set of distinct,
countable
things, like all the bricks in a certain wall, can easily be
ordered;
we need only count them off 1, 2, 3, . . . in any of dozens of different ways that will suggest themselves. But how would we go about
ordering
all the points on a straight line? They cannot be counted off 1, 2, 3, . . . . The task appears hopeless when we consider that between
any
two points of the line “we can find,” or “there exists”
another
point of the line. If every time we counted two adjacent bricks another sprang into being between them in the wall our counting would become slightly confused. Nevertheless the points on a straight line do appear to have some sort of order; we can say whether one point is to the right or the left of another, and so on. Attempts to order the points of a line have not succeeded. Zermelo proposed his postulate as a means for making the attempt easier, but it itself is not universally accepted as a reasonable assumption or as one which it is safe to use.

Cantor's theory contains a great deal more about the actual infinite and the “arithmetic” of transfinite (infinite) numbers than what has been indicated here. But as the theory is still in the controversial stage, we may leave it with the statement of a last riddle. Does there “exist,” or can we “construct,” an infinite set which is not similar (technical sense of one-to-one matching) either to the set of all the positive rational integers or to the set of all points of a line? The answer is unknown.

Cantor died in a mental hospital in Halle on January
6,
1918, at the age of seventy three. Honors and recognition were his at the last, and even the old bitterness against Kronecker was forgotten. It was no doubt a satisfaction to Cantor to recall that he and Kronecker had become at least superficially reconciled some years before Kronecker's death in 1891. Could Cantor have lived till today he might have taken a just pride in the movement toward more rigorous thinking in
all
mathematics for which his own efforts to found analysis (and the infinite) on a sound basis were largely responsible.

*  *  *

Looking back over the long struggle to make the concepts of
real number, continuity, limit,
and
infinity
precise and consistently usable in mathematics, we see that Zeno and Eudoxus were not so far in time from Weierstrass, Dedekind, and Cantor as the twenty four or twenty five centuries which separate modern Germany from ancient Greece might seem to imply. There is no doubt that we have a clearer conception of the nature of the difficulties involved than our predecessors had, because we see the same unsolved problems cropping up in new guises and in fields the ancients never dreamed of, but to say that we have disposed of those hoary old difficulties is a gross mis-statement of fact. Nevertheless the net score records a greater gain than any which our predecessors could rightfully claim. We are going deeper than they ever imagined necessary, and we are discovering that some of the “laws”—for instance those of Aristotelian logic—which they accepted in their reasoning are better replaced by others—pure conventions—in our attempts to correlate our experiences. As has already been said, Cantor's revolutionary work gave our present activity its initial impulse. But it was soon discovered—twenty one years before Cantor's death—that his revolution was either too revolutionary or not revolutionary enough. The latter now appears to be the case.

The first shot in the counter-revolution was fired in 1897 by the Italian mathematician Burali-Forti who produced a flagrant contradiction by reasoning of the type used by Cantor in his theory of infinite sets. This particular paradox was only the first of several, and as it would require lengthy explanations to make it intelligible, we shall state instead Russell's of 1908.

We have already mentioned Frege, who gave the “class of all classes similar to a given class” definition of the cardinal number of the given class. Frege had spent years trying to put the mathematics of numbers on a sound logical basis. His life work is his
Grundgesetze der Arithmetik
(The Fundamental Laws of Arithmetic), of which the first volume was published in 1893, the second in 1903. In this work the concept of sets is used. There is also a considerable use of more or less sarcastic invective against previous writers on the foundations of
arithmetic for their manifest blunders and manifold stupidities. The second volume closes with the following acknowledgment.

“A scientist can hardly encounter anything more undesirable than to have the foundation collapse just as the work is finished. I was put in this position by a letter from Mr. Bertrand Russell when the work was almost through the press.”

*  *  *

Russell had sent Frege his ingenious paradox of “the set of all sets which are not members of themselves.” Is this set a member of itself? Either answer can be puzzled out with a little thought to be wrong. Yet Frege had freely used “sets of all sets.”

Many ways were proposed for evading or eliminating the contradictions which began exploding like a barrage in and over the Frege-Dedekind-Cantor theory of the real numbers, continuity, and the infinite. Frege, Cantor, and Dedekind quit the field, beaten and disheartened. Russell proposed his “vicious circle principle” as a remedy: “Whatever involves all of a collection must not be one of the collection”; later he put forth his “axiom of reducibility,” which, as it is now practically abandoned, need not be described. For a time these restoratives were brilliantly effective (except in the opinion of the German mathematicians, who never swallowed them). Gradually, as the critical examination of all mathematical reasoning gained headway, physic was thrown to the dogs and a concerted effort was begun to find out what really ailed the patient in his irrational and real number system before administering further nostrums.

The present effort to understand our difficulties originated in the work of David Hilbert (1862-) of Göttingen in 1899 and in that of L. E. J. Brouwer (1881-) of Amsterdam in 1912. Both of these men and their numerous followers have the common purpose of putting mathematical reasoning on a sound basis, although in several respects their methods and philosophies are violently opposed. It seems unlikely that both can be as wholly right as each appears to believe he is.

Hilbert returned to Greece for the beginning of his philosophy of mathematics. Resuming the Pythagorean program of a rigidly and fully stated set of postulates from which a mathematical argument must proceed by strict deductive reasoning, Hilbert made the program of the
postulational
development of mathematics more precise than it had been with the Greeks, and in 1899 issued the first edition of his classic on the foundations of geometry. One demand which Hilbert
made, and which the Greeks do not seem to have thought of, was that the proposed postulates for geometry shall be
proved
to be self-consistent (free of internal, concealed contradictions). To produce such a proof for geometry it is shown that any contradiction in the geometry developed from the postulates would imply a contradiction in arithmetic. The problem is thus shoved back to proving the consistency of arithmetic, and there it remains today.

Thus we are back once more asking the sphinx to tell us what a number is. Both Dedekind and Frege fled to the infinite—Dedekind with his infinite classes defining irrationals, Frege with his class of all classes similar to a given class defining a cardinal number—to interpret the numbers that puzzled Pythagoras. Hilbert, too, would seek the answer in the infinite which, he believes, is necessary for an understanding of the finite. He is quite emphatic in his belief that Cantorism will ultimately be redeemed from the purgatory in which it now tosses. “This [Gan tor's theory] seems to me the most admirable fruit of the mathematical mind and indeed one of the highest achievements of man's intellectual processes.” But he admits that the paradoxes of Burali-Forti, Russell, and others are not resolved. However, his faith surmounts all doubts: “No one shall expel us from the paradise which Cantor has created for us.”

But at this moment of exaltation Brouwer appears with something that looks suspiciously like a flaming sword in his strong right hand. The chase is on: Dedekind, in the role of Adam, and Cantor disguised as Eve at his side, are already eyeing the gate apprehensively under the stern regard of the uncompromising Dutchman. The postulational method for securing freedom from contradiction proposed by Hilbert will, says Brouwer, accomplish its end—produce no contradictions,
but
“nothing of mathematical value will be attained in this manner; a false theory which is not stopped by a contradiction is none the less false, just as a criminal policy unchecked by a reprimanding court is none the less criminal.”

The root of Brouwer's objection to the “criminal policy” of his opponents is something new—at least in mathematics. He objects to an unrestricted use of Aristotelian logic, particularly in dealing with
infinite
sets, and he maintains that such logic is bound to produce contradictions when applied to sets which cannot be definitely
constructed
in Kronecker's sense (a rule of procedure must be given whereby the things in the set can be produced). The law of “excluded middle” (a
thing must have a certain property or must not have that property, as for example in the assertion that a number is prime or is not prime) is legitimately usable only when applied to
finite
sets. Aristotle devised his logic as a body of working rules for finite sets, basing his method on human experience of
finite
sets, and there is no reason whatever for supposing that a logic which is adequate for
the finite
will continue to produce consistent (not contradictory) results when applied to the
infinite.
This seems reasonable enough when we recall that the very definition of an infinite set emphasizes that a
part
of an
infinite
set may contain precisely
as many
things as the
whole
set (as we have illustrated many times), a situation which
never
happens for a finite set when “part” means
some, but not all
(as it does in the definition of an infinite set).

Here we have what some consider the root of the trouble in Cantor's theory of the actual infinite. For the
definition
of a set (as stated some time back), by which
all
things having a certain quality are “united” to form a “set” (or “class”), is not suitable as a basis for the theory of sets, in that the definition either is
not constructive
(in Kronecker's sense) or
assumes
a constructibility which no mortal can produce. Brouwer claims that the use of the law of excluded middle in such a situation is at best merely a heuristic guide to propositions which
may be
true, but which are not necessarily so, even when they have been deduced by a rigid application of Aristotelian logic, and he says that numerous false theories (including Cantor's) have been erected on this rotten foundation during the past half century.

Such a revolution in the rudiments of mathematical thinking does not go unchallenged. Brouwer's radical move to the left is speeded by an outraged roar from the reactionary right. “What Weyl and Brouwer are doing [Brouwer is the leader, Weyl his companion in revolt] is mainly following in the steps of Kronecker,” according to Hilbert, the champion of the status quo. “They are trying to establish mathematics by jettisoning everything which does not suit them and setting up an embargo. The effect is to dismember our science and to run the risk of losing a large part of our most valuable possessions. Weyl and Brouwer condemn the general notions of irrational numbers, of functions—even of such functions as occur in the theory of numbers—Cantor's transfinite numbers, etc., the theorem that an infinite set of positive integers has a least, and even the 'law of excluded middle,' as for example the assertion: Either there is only a
finite number of primes or there are infinitely many. These are examples of
[to
them] forbidden theorems and modes of reasoning. I believe that impotent as Kronecker was to abolish irrational numbers (Weyl and Brouwer do permit us to retain a torso), no less impotent will their efforts prove today. No! Brouwer's program is not a revolution, but merely the repetition of a futile
coup de main
with old methods, but which was then undertaken with greater verve, yet failed utterly. Today the State [mathematics] is thoroughly armed and strengthened through the labors of Frege, Dedekind, and Cantor. The efforts of Brouwer and Weyl are foredoomed to futility.”

Other books

Claiming Sunshine by Leonard, S. E.
Open House by Elizabeth Berg
A Reign of Steel by Morgan Rice
The Eternity Key by Bree Despain
Fields of Home by Ralph Moody
Dirty Twisted Love by Lili Valente