Overruled (13 page)

Read Overruled Online

Authors: Damon Root

BOOK: Overruled
5.53Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

But all that changed with the 1965 case of
Griswold v. Connecticut.
Two agents of the state's Planned Parenthood League, one of whom was a doctor, had been duly charged with dispensing birth-control information and devices to married couples. The Supreme Court saw its opportunity to rule on the matter and tackled the case head-on.

The result was a fractured ruling that continues to spark debate. At the heart of the case was a deceptively simple question: Does the Constitution protect a right to privacy that covers the freedom of married couples to use birth control? A majority of the Court held that it did, but then quickly divided over precisely how the Constitution managed to do it. Writing for a five-justice majority, Justice William O. Douglas argued that while the right to privacy is not specifically enumerated in the text of the document, various textual provisions do nonetheless protect certain aspects of privacy, such as the Fourth Amendment's guarantee against unreasonable searches and seizures and the Fifth Amendment's protection against self-incrimination. Furthermore, Douglas argued, those “specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have penumbras [shadows], formed by emanations from those guarantees that help give them life and substance.”
38
Taken together, the “penumbras” and “emanations” of these “fundamental constitutional
guarantees” create a distinct “zone of privacy”
39
that is itself a constitutional right worthy of judicial protection. “Would we allow the police to search the sacred precincts of marital bedrooms for telltale signs of the use of contraceptives?” he asked. “The very idea is repulsive to the notions of privacy surrounding the marriage relationship.”
40

In a separate concurrence, Justice Arthur Goldberg, joined by Chief Justice Earl Warren and Justice William Brennan, agreed that the law “unconstitutionally intrudes upon the right of marital privacy,” but instead rested the case more squarely on the language of the Ninth Amendment, which holds, “The enumeration in the Constitution of certain rights shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people.” As Goldberg saw it, privacy was clearly among those unenumerated rights retained by the married people of Connecticut. “Although the Constitution does not speak in so many words of the right of privacy in marriage,” he wrote, “I cannot believe that it offers these fundamental rights no protection.”
41

Meanwhile, two other justices, John M. Harlan and Byron White, each filed their own separate concurring opinions that rejected the penumbras approach entirely and ruled against the law solely under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. In short, the Court's liberal majority very much wanted to recognize a constitutional right to privacy, but the justices could not reach any sort of broad agreement over the proper method for doing so.

Why the disarray? Consider again the central proposition of Footnote Four from the 1938
Carolene Products
decision. It said that the Supreme Court may only engage in “exacting judicial scrutiny” when the law under review appears to violate a specific provision of the Constitution, interfere with the political process, or discriminate against “discrete and insular minorities.” Simply put, Connecticut's intrusion on marital privacy failed
42
to clearly satisfy any one of those three separate tests, leaving the justices scrambling for a fix.

Douglas in particular struggled to meet the requirements of Footnote Four. Keep in mind that
Carolene Products
was written in large part as a reaction to cases such as
Lochner v. New York,
which struck down a maximum working hours law for bakery employees,
and
Adkins v. Children's Hospital,
which struck down a minimum wage law for women. In each of those cases, the Supreme Court had nullified an economic regulation for violating the unenumerated right to liberty of contract, a right the Court first located in the Fourteenth Amendment's guarantee that no person be deprived of life, liberty, or property without due process of law. Yet as Chief Justice Charles Evans Hughes had declared in
West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish,
the 1937 case that overruled
Adkins
and effectively killed
Lochner,
“The Constitution does not speak of freedom of contract,”
43
and therefore the Supreme Court would neither recognize it nor protect it. Well, the Constitution does not speak of privacy either, and according to both
Parrish
and Footnote Four, that textual absence was a big problem for Douglas and his
Griswold
opinion.

Nor did Douglas do himself any favors when it came to the crafting of his legal arguments. On the one hand, he began his opinion by repudiating the liberty of contract line of cases. “Overtones of some arguments suggest that
Lochner v. New York
should be our guide. But we decline that invitation,”
44
he wrote. Yet just two paragraphs later, Douglas proceeded to follow
Lochner
anyway when he cited two precedents from the 1920s,
Meyer v. Nebraska
and
Pierce v. Society of Sisters,
in which the Supreme Court relied directly on
Lochner
's expansive protection of liberty in order to reach its respective holdings. In
Meyer,
for instance, Justice James C. McReynolds nullified Nebraska's ban on teaching young students in a foreign language on the grounds that it interfered with the economic liberty of a Bible teacher who worked at a private school. “Without doubt,” McReynolds wrote, citing
Lochner,
the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment “denotes not
merely freedom from bodily restraint, but also the right of the individual to contract, to engage in any of the common occupations of life . . . and generally to enjoy those privileges long recognized at common law as essential to the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men.”
45
Two years later, in
Pierce,
McReynolds extended that libertarian principle to overturn Oregon's Compulsory Education Act, which had forbidden parents from educating their children in private schools. “The child is not the mere creature of the state,”
46
McReynolds declared. Whether Justice Douglas wanted to admit it or not,
Lochner
's DNA is plainly evident in his
Griswold
opinion.

“I Like My Privacy As Well as the Next One”

For Justice Hugo Black, enough was enough.
Griswold
was a
Lochner-
ian ruling, and Black had no qualms about denouncing it as such. An ardent New Dealer when he joined the Supreme Court in 1938, the former Alabama senator was outraged by the reappearance of those old legal arguments on behalf of new unwritten rights. “I like my privacy as well as the next one,” Black declared in his
Griswold
dissent, “but I am nevertheless compelled to admit that government has a right to invade it unless prohibited by some specific constitutional provision.”
47

That remark captures Black's entire jurisprudence in a nutshell. Nobody's idea of a judicial pacifist, Black would only countenance judicial review in those cases where he thought the law at issue conflicted with an express guarantee of the Constitution. “When judges have a constitutional question in a case before them, and the public interest calls for its decision,” he would announce, “refusal to carry out their duty to decide would not, I think, be the exercise of an enviable ‘self-restraint.' Instead I would consider it to be an evasion of responsibility.”
48

In fact, when it came to the protections spelled out in the Bill of Rights, Black took a nearly absolutist position in favor of judicial intervention. In his famous 1947 dissent in
Adamson v. California,
for instance, Black argued that not only should the Fifth Amendment's safeguard against self-incrimination be strongly defended against the actions of a state government, the entire Bill of Rights should be applied to the states and aggressively enforced by the federal courts. As for the First Amendment, Black took an even harder stance. “Courts must never allow this protection to be diluted or weakened in any way,” he maintained. The First Amendment means exactly what it says, and that meaning must be protected by the courts, “without deviation, without exception, without any ifs, buts, or whereases.”
49

But when it came to the judicial enforcement of unenumerated rights, Black drew a bright line in the opposite direction and simply refused to cross it. “I cannot accept a due process clause interpretation which permits life-appointed judges to write their own economic and political views into our Constitution,”
50
he argued, thereby linking the Court's ruling in
Griswold
to its previous decision in
Lochner.
Indeed, Black's
Griswold
dissent took direct aim at Douglas's use of the libertarian precedents set in
Meyer
and
Pierce,
“both decided in opinions by Mr. Justice McReynolds,” Black noted, “which elaborated the same natural law due process philosophy found in
Lochner v. New York.
” That approach, he told his colleagues, “is no less dangerous when used to enforce this Court's views about personal rights than those about economic rights.”
51

Much like Learned Hand and Felix Frankfurter, Hugo Black never forgot his outrage over the Supreme Court's earlier use of the Fourteenth Amendment to attack Progressive and New Deal era legislation. “There is a tendency now among some,” Black observed in 1968, “to look to the judiciary to make all the major policy decisions of our society under the guise of determining constitutionality. . . . To
the people who have such faith in our nine justices, I say that I have known a different court from the one today. What has occurred may occur again.”
52

Unhappily for these old-line Progressives, however, the call for judicial deference fell on increasingly deaf liberal ears as the twentieth century entered its seventh decade. But there was at least one person paying careful attention to what they had to say. At Yale Law School, a young professor named Robert Bork began dusting off the Progressive case for judicial restraint and refurbishing it into an intellectual weapon he might wield on behalf of conservative legal goals.

Majorities Rule

Here's a surprising fact about Robert Bork: The famous arch-conservative initially welcomed the Supreme Court's decision legalizing birth control in
Griswold v. Connecticut.
Born in Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania, in 1927, Bork received an undergraduate education at the University of Chicago and then stuck around on campus to attend law school, graduating with a law degree in 1953. At that time, the University of Chicago was first solidifying its reputation as a bastion of free-market thought, thanks in large part to the work of economics professor and future Nobel Prize winner Milton Friedman, who championed minimal government interference in all aspects of economic (and private) life and famously blamed federal policies rather than capitalist excesses for causing the Great Depression.
53
Bork's encounter with those ideas initially made him into something of a libertarian, and he began applying the insights of free-market economics to the field of antitrust law when he took up his professorship at Yale Law School in 1962.

The academic world of Yale introduced a decisive new influence on Bork's thinking, that of his law school colleague Alexander Bickel. A former law clerk to Justice Felix Frankfurter, Bickel was a brilliant
and persuasive advocate of Progressive-style judicial restraint. In his 1962 book
The Least Dangerous Branch,
for instance, Bickel described judicial review as a “counter-majoritarian force in our system” and therefore a “deviant institution” that required stringent justification before use. “When the Supreme Court declares unconstitutional a legislative act or the action of an elected executive,” he wrote, “it thwarts the will of representatives of the actual people of the here and now.”
54
As a result, Bickel advocated a very modest role for the courts, urging judges to practice “the passive virtues”
55
and to avoid disruptive confrontations with the elected branches of government whenever it was remotely possible to do so.

“I taught a seminar with Professor Bickel starting in about 1963 or 1964,” Bork would later recall. “We taught a seminar called Constitutional Theory. I was then all in favor of
Griswold v. Connecticut.
” As Bork then saw it, if the courts would only ground their reasoning in the principles of individual autonomy that served as the foundation for the Bill of Rights, new rights such as privacy might be properly recognized and defended by the judiciary. “I did that for about 6 or 7 years,” Bork remembered, “and Bickel fought me every step of the way; said it was not possible. At the end of 6 or 7 years, I decided he was right.”
56
That decision transformed Bork's career and changed the future of American law.

Bork went public with his case against
Griswold
in a 1971 article for the
Indiana Law Review
titled “Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems.” It remains one of the most influential and frequently cited law review articles to appear in the last four decades. It also set the tone for all subsequent conservative attacks on liberal judicial activism. The “proper role of the Supreme Court under the Constitution” is the central question of American jurisprudence, Bork observed. “It arises when any court either exercises or declines to exercise the power to invalidate any act of another branch of government.
The Supreme Court is a major power center, and we must ask when its power should be used and when it should be withheld.”
57

Other books

Jamie's Revenge by Jenny Penn
The Gazing Globe by Candace Sams
Ninth Key by Meg Cabot
Captured by the Highlander by MacLean, Julianne
The Patriot's Conquest by Vanak, Bonnie
Fire Along the Sky by Sara Donati
The Dirty Divorce by KP, Miss
Dangerous Bond (Jamie Bond Mysteries Book 4) by Halliday, Gemma, Fischetto, Jennifer
Wittgenstein Jr by Lars Iyer