The Flamingo’s Smile (36 page)

Read The Flamingo’s Smile Online

Authors: Stephen Jay Gould

BOOK: The Flamingo’s Smile
5.53Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

The improbabilities of history proclaim that all species are unique and unrepeatable in detail. Evolutionary theory, as a science of history, does deny the specific argument for humanoids on other worlds. All leading evolutionists, in their writings on exobiology, have said so with gusto, and I agree. Wallace began the theme in 1903:

The ultimate development of man has, therefore roughly speaking, depended on something like a million distinct modifications, each of a special type and dependent on some precedent changes in the organic and inorganic environments, or in both. The chances against such an enormously long series of definite modifications having occurred twice over…are almost infinite.

Simpson has expressed the theme most eloquently in recent years, in his famous essay on “the nonprevalence of humanoids” (see bibliography):

This essential nonrepeatability of evolution on earth obviously has a decisive bearing on the chances that it has been repeated or closely paralleled on any other planet. The assumption, so freely made by astronomers, physicists, and some biochemists, that once life gets started anywhere, humanoids will eventually and inevitably appear is plainly false…. Let us grant the unsubstantiated claim of millions or billions of possible planetary abodes of life; the chances of such historical duplication are still vanishingly small.

But all these evolutionists have also clearly distinguished this specific proposition about humanoids from the general argument that intelligence in some other form might arise elsewhere. On the general proposition, they have maintained a diversity of opinions—leading to the empirical conclusion that “evolutionary theory” has no clear pronouncement to make. Both Wallace and Simpson extended their argument to doubt the general claim as well, but ever so much more gently, and as a personal opinion only. Simpson, for example, wrote:

Even in planetary histories different from ours might not some quite different and yet comparably intelligent beings…have evolved? Obviously these are questions that cannot be answered categorically. I can only express an opinion…I think it extremely unlikely that anything enough like us for real communication of thought exists anywhere in our accessible universe.

Other evolutionists, however, including two cited by Tipler as denying any possibility for SETTs success, also distinguish the specific from the general argument, but express far more optimism for the generality. Dobzhansky and Ayala, in a leading textbook (coauthored with G.L. Stebbins and J.W. Valentine), write (see bibliography):

Granting that the possibility of obtaining a man-like creature is vanishingly small even given an astronomical number of attempts…there is still some small possibility that another intelligent species has arisen, one that is capable of achieving a technological civilization.

I am not convinced that the possibility is so small.

Does evolutionary theory offer any insight about the general argument? We gain some sense of probabilities for repetition of a basic theme (but not of specific details) from the phenomenon known as “convergence.” Flight has evolved separately in insects, birds, pterosaurs (flying reptiles), and bats. Aerodynamic principles do not change, but morphologies differ widely (birds use feathers; bats and pterosaurs employ a membrane, but bats stretch it between several fingers, pterosaurs only from one). Marsupial “moles” and “wolves” evolved on Australia, a continent isolated from placental mammals elsewhere. Since adaptive themes are limited and animals so diverse, convergence of different evolutionary lineages to the same general solution (but not to detailed repetition) are common. Highly adaptive forms that are easy to evolve arise again and again. More complex morphologies without such adaptive necessity offer little or no prospect for repetition. Conscious intelligence has evolved only once on earth, and presents no real prospect for reemergence should we choose to use our gift for destruction. But does intelligence lie within the class of phenomena too complex and historically conditioned for repetition? I do not think that its uniqueness on earth specifies such a conclusion. Perhaps, in another form on another world, intelligence would be as easy to evolve as flight on ours.

Tipler dismisses the issue of convergence by stating that biologist Leonard Ornstein (in an article supporting Tipler, see bibliography) has refuted the most famous of all convergences—the “camera eye” of vertebrates and cephalopods (squids and their allies)—by suggesting that this structure arose in both groups from a common ancestor, and not separately in each. Even if Ornstein were right, the dismissal of a specific case does not deny the importance of convergence as a general phenomenon. But Ornstein’s arguments are seriously flawed. He never mentions the strongest, “classical” argument for convergence—that the eyes, although so similar in design and operation, develop embryologically in fundamentally different ways (squid eyes form from skin precursors, while vertebrate eyes, the lens excepted, develop from the brain). Moreover, Ornstein’s main argument for evolution from a common ancestor relies upon a biological principle disproved more than fifty years ago. He invokes Haeckel’s discredited law that “ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny”—that an organism’s embryological development repeats the sequence of ancestral adults in its evolutionary lineage. Since the eye develops so early in embryology, Ornstein argues that it may have already existed in a very remote ancestor—early enough to predate the evolutionary split of vertebrate and squid lineages. Not only has Haeckel’s law been disproved (embryos do not repeat ancestral stages), but even Haeckel himself, in the heyday of his principle, rarely used time of appearance in embryology to specify moment of evolutionary origin—for he himself had identified and named a large class of exceptions to such a facile generality.

Even if we follow Tipler in arguing that von Neumann machines are the only proper way to go, he admits that we won’t have the technology to build one for a century. I’m an impatient and mortal fellow. As I think it cruel to ask disadvantaged minorities to “go slow” in demands for political change—thus guaranteeing that any practical benefits will fall only upon their children’s children—so too do I selfishly wish to see some exobiological results (positive or negative) in my lifetime. SETI is all we have for now. It is relatively cheap, and (in my view) entirely sensible from those perspectives that evolutionary theory can enlighten. Frankly, I think the chances of its success are a good deal lower than the probabilities envisioned by its more enthusiastic supporters among physical scientists. But we can’t know until we try. Ultimately, however, I must justify the attempt at such a long shot simply by stating that a positive result would be the most cataclysmic event in our entire intellectual history. Curiosity impels, and makes us human. Might it impel others as well?

8 | Extinction and Continuity
28 | Sex, Drugs, Disasters, and the Extinction of Dinosaurs

SCIENCE, IN ITS MOST
fundamental definition, is a fruitful mode of inquiry, not a list of enticing conclusions. The conclusions are the consequence, not the essence.

My greatest unhappiness with most popular presentations of science concerns their failure to separate fascinating claims from the methods that scientists use to establish the facts of nature. Journalists, and the public, thrive on controversial and stunning statements. But science is, basically, a way of knowing—in P.B. Medawar’s apt words, “the art of the soluble.” If the growing corps of popular science writers would focus on
how
scientists develop and defend those fascinating claims, they would make their greatest possible contribution to public understanding.

Consider three ideas, proposed in perfect seriousness to explain that greatest of all titillating puzzles—the extinction of dinosaurs. Since these three notions invoke the primally fascinating themes of our culture—sex, drugs, and violence—they surely reside in the category of fascinating claims. I want to show why two of them rank as silly speculation, while the other represents science at its grandest and most useful.

Science works with testable proposals. If, after much compilation and scrutiny of data, new information continues to affirm a hypothesis, we may accept it provisionally and gain confidence as further evidence mounts. We can never be completely sure that a hypothesis is right, though we may be able to show with confidence that it is wrong. The best scientific hypotheses are also generous and expansive: they suggest extensions and implications that enlighten related, and even far distant, subjects. Simply consider how the idea of evolution has influenced virtually every intellectual field.

Useless speculation, on the other hand, is restrictive. It generates no testable hypothesis, and offers no way to obtain potentially refuting evidence. Please note that I am not speaking of truth or falsity. The speculation may well be true; still, if it provides, in principle, no material for affirmation or rejection, we can make nothing of it. It must simply stand forever as an intriguing idea. Useless speculation turns in on itself and leads nowhere; good science, containing both seeds for its potential refutation and implications for more and different testable knowledge, reaches out. But, enough preaching. Let’s move on to dinosaurs, and the three proposals for their extinction.

  1. Sex: Testes function only in a narrow range of temperature (those of mammals hang externally in a scrotal sac because internal body temperatures are too high for their proper function). A worldwide rise in temperature at the close of the Cretaceous period caused the testes of dinosaurs to stop functioning and led to their extinction by sterilization of males.
  2. Drugs: Angiosperms (flowering plants) first evolved toward the end of the dinosaurs’ reign. Many of these plants contain psychoactive agents, avoided by mammals today as a result of their bitter taste. Dinosaurs had neither means to taste the bitterness nor livers effective enough to detoxify the substances. They died of massive overdoses.
  3. Disasters: A large comet or asteroid struck the earth some 65 million years ago, lofting a cloud of dust into the sky and blocking sunlight, thereby suppressing photosynthesis and so drastically lowering world temperatures that dinosaurs and hosts of other creatures became extinct.

Before analyzing these three tantalizing statements, we must establish a basic ground rule often violated in proposals for the dinosaurs’ demise.
There is no separate problem of the extinction of dinosaurs
. Too often we divorce specific events from their wider contexts and systems of cause and effect. The fundamental fact of dinosaur extinction is its synchrony with the demise of so many other groups across a wide range of habitats, from terrestrial to marine.

The history of life has been punctuated by brief episodes of mass extinction. A recent analysis by University of Chicago paleontologists Jack Sepkoski and Dave Raup, based on the best and most exhaustive tabulation of data ever assembled, shows clearly that five episodes of mass dying stand well above the “background” extinctions of normal times (when we consider all mass extinctions, large and small, they seem to fall in a regular 26-million-year cycle—see essay 30). The Cretaceous debacle, occurring 65 million years ago and separating the Mesozoic and Cenozoic eras of our geological time scale, ranks prominently among the five. Nearly all the marine plankton (single-celled floating creatures) died with geological suddenness; among marine invertebrates, nearly 15 percent of all families perished, including many previously dominant groups, especially the ammonites (relatives of squids in coiled shells). On land, the dinosaurs disappeared after more than 100 million years of unchallenged domination.

In this context, speculations limited to dinosaurs alone ignore the larger phenomenon. We need a coordinated explanation for a system of events that includes the extinction of dinosaurs as one component. Thus it makes little sense, though it may fuel our desire to view mammals as inevitable inheritors of the earth, to guess that dinosaurs died because small mammals ate their eggs (a perennial favorite among untestable speculations). It seems most unlikely that some disaster peculiar to dinosaurs befell these massive beasts—and that the debacle happened to strike just when one of history’s five great dyings had enveloped the earth for completely different reasons.

The testicular theory, an old favorite from the 1940s, had its root in an interesting and thoroughly respectable study of temperature tolerances in the American alligator, published in the staid
Bulletin of the American Museum of Natural History
in 1946 by three experts on living and fossil reptiles—E.H. Colbert, my own first teacher in paleontology; R.B. Cowles; and C.M. Bogert.

The first sentence of their summary reveals a purpose beyond alligators: “This report describes an attempt to infer the reactions of extinct reptiles, especially the dinosaurs, to high temperatures as based upon reactions observed in the modern alligator.” They studied, by rectal thermometry, the body temperatures of alligators under changing conditions of heating and cooling. (Well, let’s face it, you wouldn’t want to try sticking a thermometer under a ’gator’s tongue.) The predictions under test go way back to an old theory first stated by Galileo in the 1630s—the unequal scaling of surfaces and volumes. As an animal, or any object, grows (provided its shape doesn’t change), surface areas must increase more slowly than volumes—since surfaces get larger as length squared, while volumes increase much more rapidly, as length cubed. Therefore, small animals have high ratios of surface to volume, while large animals cover themselves with relatively little surface.

Among cold-blooded animals lacking any physiological mechanism for keeping their temperatures constant, small creatures have a hell of a time keeping warm—because they lose so much heat through their relatively large surfaces. On the other hand, large animals, with their relatively small surfaces, may lose heat so slowly that, once warm, they may maintain effectively constant temperatures against ordinary fluctuations of climate. (In fact, the resolution of the “hot-blooded dinosaur” controversy that burned so brightly a few years back may simply be that, while large dinosaurs possessed no physiological mechanism for constant temperature, and were not therefore warm-blooded in the technical sense, their large size and relatively small surface area kept them warm.)

Colbert, Cowles, and Bogert compared the warming rates of small and large alligators. As predicted, the small fellows heated up (and cooled down) more quickly. When exposed to a warm sun, a tiny 50-gram (1.76-ounce) alligator heated up one degree Celsius every minute and a half, while a large alligator, 260 times bigger at 13,000 grams (28.7 pounds), took seven and a half minutes to gain a degree. Extrapolating up to an adult 10-ton dinosaur, they concluded that a one-degree rise in body temperature would take eighty-six hours. If large animals absorb heat so slowly (through their relatively small surfaces), they will also be unable to shed any excess heat gained when temperatures rise above a favorable level.

The authors then guessed that large dinosaurs lived at or near their optimum temperatures; Cowles suggested that a rise in global temperatures just before the Cretaceous extinction caused the dinosaurs to heat up beyond their optimal tolerance—and, being so large, they couldn’t shed the unwanted heat. (In a most unusual statement within a scientific paper, Colbert and Bogert then explicitly disavowed this speculative extension of their empirical work on alligators.) Cowles conceded that this excess heat probably wasn’t enough to kill or even to enervate the great beasts, but since testes often function only within a narrow range of temperature, he proposed that this global rise might have sterilized all the males, causing extinction by natural contraception.

The overdose theory has recently been supported by UCLA psychiatrist Ronald K. Siegel. Siegel has gathered, he claims, more than 2,000 records of animals who, when given access, administer various drugs to themselves—from a mere swig of alcohol to massive doses of the big H. Elephants will swill the equivalent of twenty beers at a time, but do not like alcohol in concentrations greater than 7 percent. In a silly bit of anthropocentric speculation, Siegel states that “elephants drink, perhaps, to forget…the anxiety produced by shrinking rangeland and the competition for food.”

Since fertile imaginations can apply almost any hot idea to the extinction of dinosaurs, Siegel found a way. Flowering plants did not evolve until late in the dinosaurs’ reign. These plants also produced an array of aromatic, amino-acid-based alkaloids—the major group of psychoactive agents. Most mammals are “smart” enough to avoid these potential poisons. The alkaloids simply don’t taste good (they are bitter); in any case, we mammals have livers happily supplied with the capacity to detoxify them. But, Siegel speculates, perhaps dinosaurs could neither taste the bitterness nor detoxify the substances once ingested. He recently told members of the American Psychological Association: “I’m not suggesting that all dinosaurs OD’d on plant drugs, but it certainly was a factor.” He also argued that death by overdose may help explain why so many dinosaur fossils are found in contorted positions. (Do not go gentle into that good night.)

Extraterrestrial catastrophes have long pedigrees in the popular literature of extinction, but the subject exploded again in 1979, after a long lull, when the father-son, physicist-geologist team of Luis and Walter Alvarez proposed that an asteroid, some 10 km in diameter, struck the earth 65 million years ago (comets, rather than asteroids, have since gained favor for reasons outlined in essay 30. Good science is self-corrective).

The force of such a collision would be immense, greater by far than the megatonnage of all the world’s nuclear weapons (see essay 29). In trying to reconstruct a scenario that would explain the simultaneous dying of dinosaurs on land and so many creatures in the sea, the Alvarezes proposed that a gigantic dust cloud, generated by particles blown aloft in the impact, would so darken the earth that photosynthesis would cease and temperatures drop precipitously. (Rage, rage against the dying of the light.) The single-celled photosynthetic oceanic plankton, with life cycles measured in weeks, would perish outright, but land plants might survive through the dormancy of their seeds (land plants were not much affected by the Cretaceous extinction, and any adequate theory must account for the curious pattern of differential survival). Dinosaurs would die by starvation and freezing; small, warm-blooded mammals, with more modest requirements for food and better regulation of body temperature, would squeak through. “Let the bastards freeze in the dark,” as bumper stickers of our chauvinistic neighbors in sunbelt states proclaimed several years ago during the Northeast’s winter oil crisis.

All three theories, testicular malfunction, psychoactive overdosing, and asteroidal zapping, grab our attention mightily. As pure phenomenology, they rank about equally high on any hit parade of primal fascination. Yet one represents expansive science, the others restrictive and untestable speculation. The proper criterion lies in evidence and methodology; we must probe behind the superficial fascination of particular claims.

How could we possibly decide whether the hypothesis of testicular frying is right or wrong? We would have to know things that the fossil record cannot provide. What temperatures were optimal for dinosaurs? Could they avoid the absorption of excess heat by staying in the shade, or in caves? At what temperatures did their testicles cease to function? Were late Cretaceous climates ever warm enough to drive the internal temperatures of dinosaurs close to this ceiling? Testicles simply don’t fossilize, and how could we infer their temperature tolerances even if they did? In short, Cowles’s hypothesis is only an intriguing speculation leading nowhere. The most damning statement against it appeared right in the conclusion of Colbert, Cowles, and Bogert’s paper, when they admitted: “It is difficult to advance any definite arguments against this hypothesis.” My statement may seem paradoxical—isn’t a hypothesis really good if you can’t devise any arguments against it? Quite the contrary. It is simply untestable and unusable.

Siegel’s overdosing has even less going for it. At least Cowles extrapolated his conclusion from some good data on alligators. And he didn’t completely violate the primary guideline of siting dinosaur extinction in the context of a general mass dying—for rise in temperature could be the root cause of a general catastrophe, zapping dinosaurs by testicular malfunction and different groups for other reasons. But Siegel’s speculation cannot touch the extinction of ammonites or oceanic plankton (diatoms make their own food with good sweet sunlight; they don’t OD on the chemicals of terrestrial plants). It is simply a gratuitous, attentiongrabbing guess. It cannot be tested, for how can we know what dinosaurs tasted and what their livers could do? Livers don’t fossilize any better than testicles.

The hypothesis doesn’t even make any sense in its own context. Angiosperms were in full flower ten million years before dinosaurs went the way of all flesh. Why did it take so long? As for the pains of a chemical death recorded in contortions of fossils, I regret to say (or rather I’m pleased to note for the dinosaurs’ sake) that Siegel’s knowledge of geology must be a bit deficient: muscles contract after death and geological strata rise and fall with motions of the earth’s crust after burial—more than enough reason to distort a fossil’s pristine appearance.

Other books

The Path of Daggers by Jordan, Robert
Choice Theory by William Glasser, M.D.
Allison Hewitt Is Trapped by Madeleine Roux
False Notes by Carolyn Keene
La Suite by M. P. Franck
Fireman Dodge by Penelope Rivers
A Princess of Landover by Terry Brooks
The Advocate's Wife by Norman Russell