Read The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology Online

Authors: Ray Kurzweil

Tags: #Non-Fiction, #Fringe Science, #Retail, #Technology, #Amazon.com

The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology (74 page)

BOOK: The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology
10.55Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Freitas has identified a number of other disastrous nanobot scenarios.
17
In what he calls the “gray plankton” scenario, malicious nanobots would use underwater carbon stored as CH
4
(methane) as well as CO
2
dissolved in seawater. These ocean-based sources can provide about ten times as much carbon as Earth’s biomass. In his “gray dust” scenario, replicating nanobots use basic elements available in airborne dust and sunlight for power. The “gray lichens” scenario involves using carbon and other elements on rocks.

A Panoply of Existential Risks

 

If a little knowledge is dangerous, where is a person who has so much as to be out of danger?

                   —T
HOMAS
H
ENRY

 

I discuss below (see the section “A Program for GNR Defense,” p.
422
) steps we can take to address these grave risks, but we cannot have complete assurance in any strategy that we devise today. These risks are what Nick Bostrom calls “existential risks,” which he defines as the dangers in the upper-right quadrant of the following table:
18

 

Bostrom’s Categorization of Risks

 

Biological life on Earth encountered a human-made existential risk for the first time in the middle of the twentieth century with the advent of the hydrogen bomb and the subsequent cold-war buildup of thermonuclear forces. President Kennedy reportedly estimated that the likelihood of an all-out nuclear war during the Cuban missile crisis was between 33 and 50 percent.
19
The legendary information theorist John von Neumann, who became the chairman of the Air Force Strategic Missiles Evaluation Committee and a government adviser on nuclear strategies, estimated the likelihood of nuclear Armageddon (prior to the Cuban missile crisis) at close to 100 percent.
20
Given the perspective of the 1960s what informed observer of those times would have predicted that the world would have gone through the next forty years without another nontest nuclear explosion?

Despite the apparent chaos of international affairs we can be grateful for the successful avoidance thus far of the employment of nuclear weapons in war. But we clearly cannot rest easily, since enough hydrogen bombs still exist to destroy all human life many times over.
21
Although attracting relatively little public discussion, the massive opposing ICBM arsenals of the United States and Russia remain in place, despite the apparent thawing of relations.

Nuclear proliferation and the widespread availability of nuclear materials and know-how is another grave concern, although not an existential one for our civilization. (That is, only an all-out thermonuclear war involving the ICBM arsenals poses a risk to survival of all humans.) Nuclear proliferation
and nuclear terrorism belong to the “profound-local” category of risk, along with genocide. However, the concern is certainly severe because the logic of mutual assured destruction does not work in the context of suicide terrorists.

Debatably we’ve now added another existential risk, which is the possibility of a bioengineered virus that spreads easily, has a long incubation period, and delivers an ultimately deadly payload. Some viruses are easily communicable, such as the flu and common cold. Others are deadly, such as HIV. It is rare for a virus to combine both attributes. Humans living today are descendants of those who developed natural immunities to most of the highly communicable viruses. The ability of the species to survive viral outbreaks is one advantage of sexual reproduction, which tends to ensure genetic diversity in the population, so that the response to specific viral agents is highly variable. Although catastrophic, bubonic plague did not kill everyone in Europe. Other viruses, such as smallpox, have both negative characteristics—they are easily contagious and deadly—but have been around long enough that there has been time for society to create a technological protection in the form of a vaccine. Gene engineering, however, has the potential to bypass these evolutionary protections by suddenly introducing new pathogens for which we have no protection, natural or technological.

The prospect of adding genes for deadly toxins to easily transmitted, common viruses such as the common cold and flu introduced another possible existential-risk scenario. It was this prospect that led to the Asilomar conference to consider how to deal with such a threat and the subsequent drafting of a set of safety and ethics guidelines. Although these guidelines have worked thus far, the underlying technologies for genetic manipulation are growing rapidly in sophistication.

In 2003 the world struggled, successfully, with the SARS virus. The emergence of SARS resulted from a combination of an ancient practice (the virus is suspected of having jumped from exotic animals, possibly civet cats, to humans living in close proximity) and a modern practice (the infection spread rapidly across the world by air travel). SARS provided us with a dry run of a virus new to human civilization that combined easy transmission, the ability to survive for extended periods of time outside the human body, and a high degree of mortality, with death rates estimated at 14 to 20 percent. Again, the response combined ancient and modern techniques.

Our experience with SARS shows that most viruses, even if relatively easily transmitted and reasonably deadly, represent grave but not necessarily existential risks. SARS, however, does not appear to have been engineered. SARS spreads easily through externally transmitted bodily fluids but is not easily spread through airborne particles. Its incubation period is estimated to range from one day to two weeks, whereas a longer incubation period would allow a
virus to spread through several exponentially growing generations before carriers are identified.
22

SARS is deadly, but the majority of its victims do survive. It continues to be feasible for a virus to be malevolently engineered so it spreads more easily than SARS, has an extended incubation period, and is deadly to essentially all victims. Smallpox is close to having these characteristics. Although we have a vaccine (albeit a crude one), the vaccine would not be effective against genetically modified versions of the virus.

As I describe below, the window of malicious opportunity for bioengineered viruses, existential or otherwise, will close in the 2020s when we have fully effective antiviral technologies based on nanobots.
23
However, because nanotechnology will be thousands of times stronger, faster, and more intelligent than biological entities, self-replicating nanobots will present a greater risk and yet another existential risk. The window for malevolent nanobots will ultimately be closed by strong artificial intelligence, but, not surprisingly, “unfriendly” AI will itself present an even more compelling existential risk, which I discuss below (see p.
420
).

The Precautionary Principle.
As Bostrom, Freitas, and other observers including myself have pointed out, we cannot rely on trial-and-error approaches to deal with existential risks. There are competing interpretations of what has become known as the “precautionary principle.” (If the consequences of an action are unknown but judged by some scientists to have even a small risk of being profoundly negative, it’s better to not carry out the action than risk negative consequences.) But it’s clear that we need to achieve the highest possible level of confidence in our strategies to combat such risks. This is one reason we’re hearing increasingly strident voices demanding that we shut down the advance of technology, as a primary strategy to eliminate new existential risks before they occur. Relinquishment, however, is not the appropriate response and will only interfere with the profound benefits of these emerging technologies while actually increasing the likelihood of a disastrous outcome. Max More articulates the limitations of the precautionary principle and advocates replacing it with what he calls the “proactionary principle,” which involves balancing the risks of action and inaction.
24

Before discussing how to respond to the new challenge of existential risks, it’s worth reviewing a few more that have been postulated by Bostrom and others.

The Smaller the Interaction, the Larger the Explosive Potential.
There has been recent controversy over the potential for future very high-energy particle accelerators to create a chain reaction of transformed energy states at a
subatomic level. The result could be an exponentially spreading area of destruction, breaking apart all atoms in our galactic vicinity. A variety of such scenarios has been proposed, including the possibility of creating a black hole that would draw in our solar system.

Analyses of these scenarios show them to be very unlikely, although not all physicists are sanguine about the danger.
25
The mathematics of these analyses appears to be sound, but we do not yet have a consensus on the formulas that describe this level of physical reality. If such dangers sound far-fetched, consider the possibility that we have indeed detected increasingly powerful explosive phenomena at diminishing scales of matter.

Alfred Nobel discovered dynamite by probing chemical interactions of molecules. The atomic bomb, which is tens of thousands of times more powerful than dynamite, is based on nuclear interactions involving large atoms, which are much smaller scales of matter than large molecules. The hydrogen bomb, which is thousands of times more powerful than an atomic bomb, is based on interactions involving an even smaller scale: small atoms. Although this insight does not necessarily imply the existence of yet more powerful destructive chain reactions by manipulating subatomic particles, it does make the conjecture plausible.

My own assessment of this danger is that we are unlikely simply to stumble across such a destructive event. Consider how unlikely it would be to accidentally produce an atomic bomb. Such a device requires a precise configuration of materials and actions, and the original required an extensive and precise engineering project to develop. Inadvertently creating a hydrogen bomb would be even less plausible. One would have to create the precise conditions of an atomic bomb in a particular arrangement with a hydrogen core and other elements. Stumbling across the exact conditions to create a new class of catastrophic chain reaction at a subatomic level appears to be even less likely. The consequences are sufficiently devastating, however, that the precautionary principle should lead us to take these possibilities seriously. This potential should be carefully analyzed prior to carrying out new classes of accelerator experiments. However, this risk is not high on my list of twenty-first-century concerns.

Our Simulation Is Turned Off.
Another existential risk that Bostrom and others have identified is that we’re actually living in a simulation and the simulation will be shut down. It might appear that there’s not a lot we could do to influence this. However, since we’re the subject of the simulation, we do have the opportunity to shape what happens inside of it. The best way we could
avoid being shut down would be to be interesting to the observers of the simulation. Assuming that someone is actually paying attention to the simulation, it’s a fair assumption that it’s less likely to be turned off when it’s compelling than otherwise.

We could spend a lot of time considering what it means for a simulation to be interesting, but the creation of new knowledge would be a critical part of this assessment. Although it may be difficult for us to conjecture what would be interesting to our hypothesized simulation observer, it would seem that the Singularity is likely to be about as absorbing as any development we could imagine and would create new knowledge at an extraordinary rate. Indeed, achieving a Singularity of exploding knowledge may be the very purpose of the simulation. Thus, assuring a “constructive” Singularity (one that avoids degenerate outcomes such as existential destruction by gray goo or dominance by a malicious AI) could be the best course to prevent the simulation from being terminated. Of course, we have every motivation to achieve a constructive Singularity for many other reasons.

If the world we’re living in is a simulation on someone’s computer, it’s a very good one—so detailed, in fact, that we may as well accept it as our reality. In any event, it is the only reality to which we have access.

Our world appears to have a long and rich history. This means that either our world is not, in fact, a simulation or, if it is, the simulation has been going a very long time and thus is not likely to stop anytime soon. Of course it is also possible that the simulation includes evidence of a long history without the history’s having actually occurred.

BOOK: The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology
10.55Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Bury the Hatchet by Catherine Gayle
Body By Night by Day, Zuri
The Bound Heart by Elsa Holland
The Orc King's Captive by Kinderton, Clea
The Book of Someday by Dianne Dixon
Hard to Handle by Raven Scott