Virtual History: Alternatives and Counterfactuals (11 page)

BOOK: Virtual History: Alternatives and Counterfactuals
2.37Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
There is only one problem with the narrative revival, and it is the perennial problem of applying literary forms to history. Literary genres are to some extent predictable: indeed, that is part of their appeal. Often, we read a favourite novel or watch a ‘classic’ film knowing exactly how it will end. And even if a piece is unknown to us - and there is no dustjacket or programme to give us the gist of the story - we can still often infer from its genre roughly how it will turn out. If a play is from the outset a comedy, we subconsciously rule out the possibility of carnage in the final act; if it is clearly a tragedy, we do the opposite. Even where an author notionally keeps the reader ‘in suspense’ - as in a detective whodunnit - the outcome is to some extent predictable: according to the conventions of the genre, a criminal will be caught, a crime solved. The professional writer writes with the ending in mind and frequently hints at it to the reader for the sake of irony, or some other effect. As Gallie has argued: ‘To follow a story ... involves ... some vague appreciation of its drift or direction ... and appreciation of how what comes later depends upon what came earlier, in the sense that but for the latter, the former could not have, or could hardly have occurred in the way that it did occur.’
146
The same point is made by Scriven: ‘A good play must develop in such a way that we ... see the development as necessary, i.e. can explain it.’
147
Martin Amis’s novel
Time’s Arrow
thus merely makes explicit what is implicit in all narratives: the end literally precedes the beginning.
148
Amis tells the life story of a Nazi doctor backwards, in the guise of a narrator within him who ‘knows something he seems unable to face: ... the future always comes true’. Thus the old man who ‘emerges’ from his death bed in an American hospital is ‘doomed’ to perform experiments on prisoners in the Nazi death camps and to ‘depart’ the world as an innocent infant. In literature, to adapt a phrase of Ernst Bloch, ‘he true genesis is not in the beginning but in the end’: time’s arrow always implicitly points the wrong way. Amis makes the point well when he describes a chess match in reverse: beginning in ‘disarray’, and going ‘through episodes of contortion and crosspurpose. But things work out. ... All that agony - it all works out. One final tug on the white pawn, and perfect order is restored.’
To write history according to the conventions of a novel or play is therefore to impose a new kind of determinism on the past: the teleology of the traditional narrative form. Gibbon, for all his awareness of contingency when considering particular events, subsumed a millennium and a half of European history under the supreme teleological title. If he had published his great work as A
History of Europe and the Middle East, AD 100-1400
rather than
The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire
, his narrative would have lost its unifying theme. Likewise Macaulay: there is an undeniable tendency in the
History of England
to present the events of the seventeenth century as leading to the constitutional arrangements of the nineteenth. This was the form of teleology which Collingwood later saw as integral to history: the assumption that the present was always the end-point (and implicitly the only possible end-point) of the historian’s chosen narrative. But (as with fiction) history written in this fashion might as well be written backwards, like the backwards history of Ireland which the writer ‘AE’ imagined in 1914:
The small holdings of the 19th and 20th centuries gradually come into the hands of the large owners, in the 18th century progress has been made and the first glimmerings of self government appear, religious troubles and wars follow until the
last
Englishman, Strongbow, leaves the country, culture begins, religious intolerance ceases with the
disappearance
of Patrick, about AD 400, and we approach the great age of the heroes and gods.
149
This, as AE himself joked, was merely the nationalist ‘mythistory’, mistakenly bound back to front.
The Garden of Forking Paths
The past - like real-life chess, or indeed any other game - is different; it does not have a predetermined end. There is no author, divine or otherwise; only characters, and (unlike in a game) a great deal too many of them. There is no plot, no inevitable ‘perfect order’; only endings, since multiple events unfold simultaneously, some lasting only moments, some extending far beyond an individual’s life. Once again, it was Robert Musil who put his finger on this essential difference between history proper and mere stories. In a chapter in
The Man without Qualities
entitled ‘Why does one not invent history?’, Ulrich - who, symbolically, is on board a tram - reflects on:
mathematical problems that did not admit of any general solution, though they did admit of particular solutions, the combining of which brought one nearer to the general solution.... [H]e regarded the problem set by every human life as one of these. What one calls an age ... this broad, unregulated flux of conditions would then amount to approximately as much as a chaotic succession of unsatisfactory and (when taken singly) false attempts at a solution, attempts that might produce the correct and total solution, but only when humanity had learnt to combine them all. ... What a strange affair history was, come to think of it.... This history of ours looks pretty safe and messy, when looked at from close at hand, something like a half-solidified swamp, and then in the end, strangely enough, it turns out there is after all a track running across it, the very ‘road of history’ of which nobody knows whence it comes. This
being the material of history
was something which made Ulrich indignant. The luminous, swaying box in which he was travelling seemed to him like a machine in which several hundred-weight of humanity were shaken to and fro in the process of being made into something called ‘the future....’ Feeling this, he revolted against this impotent putting-up-with changes and conditions, against this helpless contemporaneity, the unsystematic, submissive, indeed humanly undignified stringing-along with the centuries ... Involuntarily he got up and finished his journey on foot.
150
Ulrich rejects the possibility that ‘world history was a story that ... came into existence just the same way as all other stories’, because ‘nothing new ever occurred to authors, and one copied from another’. On the contrary, ‘history ... came into existence for the most part without any authors. It evolved not from the centre, but from the periphery, from minor causes’. Moreover, it unfolds in a fundamentally chaotic way, like an order transmitted in whispers from one end of a column of soldiers which begins as ‘Sergeant major to move to the head of the column’ but ends as ‘Eight troopers to be shot immediately’:
If one were therefore to transplant a whole generation of present-day Europeans while still in their infancy into the Egypt of the year five thousand BC, and leave them there, world history would begin all over again at the year five thousand, at first repeating itself for a while and then, for reasons that no man can guess, gradually beginning to deviate.
The law of world history was thus simply ‘muddling through’:
The course of history was ... not that of a billiard-ball, which, once it has been hit, ran along a definite course; on the contrary, it was like the passage of clouds, like the way of a man sauntering through the streets - diverted here by a shadow, there by a little crowd of people ... - finally arriving at a place that he had neither known of nor meant to reach. There was inherent in the course of history a certain element of going off course.
151
This line of argument disconcerts Ulrich - so much so (and as if to prove the point) that he loses his own way home.
In short, history is not a story any more than it is a tram journey; and historians who persist in trying to write it as a story might as well follow Amis or AE and write it backwards. The reality of history, as Musil suggests, is that the end is unknown at the beginning of the journey: there are no rails leading predictably into the future, no timetables with destinations set out in black and white. Much the same point was made by Jorge Luis Borges in his short story ‘The Garden of Forking Paths’. The author imagines a labyrinth-cum-novel devised by an imaginary Chinese sage, Ts’ui Pen, in which ‘time forks perpetually toward innumerable futures’:
‘I lingered naturally on the sentence:
I leave to the various futures (not to all) my garden of forking path
s. Almost instantly, I understood: “The garden of forking paths” was the chaotic novel; the phrase “the various futures (not to all)” suggested to me the forking in time, not in space. ... In all fictional works, each time a man is confronted with several alternatives, he chooses one and eliminates the others; in the fiction of Ts’ui Pen, he chooses - simultaneously - all of them.
He creates
, in this way, diverse futures; diverse times which themselves also proliferate and fork.... In the work of Ts‘ui Pen, all possible outcomes occur; each one is the point of departure for other forkings.’
The work’s imaginary translator goes on:
‘The Garden of Forking Paths
is an enormous riddle, or parable, whose theme is time ... an incomplete, but not false, image of the universe ... In contrast to Newton or Schopenhauer, [Ts’ui Pen] did not believe in a uniform, absolute time. He believed in an infinite series of times, in a growing, dizzying net of divergent, convergent and parallel times. This network of times which approached one another, forked, broke off, or were unaware of one another for centuries, embraces
all
possibilities of time ...’.
152
Variations on this theme recur throughout Borges’s work. In the idealists’ imaginary world described in ‘Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius’, ‘works of fiction contain a single plot with all its imaginable permutations’.
153
In ‘The Lottery in Babylon’, an imaginary ancient lottery evolves into an all-embracing way of life; what begins as ‘an intensification of chance, a periodical infusion of chaos into the universe’ becomes an infinite process in which ‘no decision is final, all branch into others’.‘Babylon is nothing less than an infinite game of chance.’
154
The metaphor is changed, but the same theme developed, in‘The Library of Babel’ and ’The Zahir’. Similar images can also be found in Mallarmé’s poem ‘Un Coup de dés’
155
or Robert Frost’s ‘The Road Not Taken’:
I shall be telling this with a sigh
Somewhere ages and ages hence:
Two roads diverged in a wood, and I -
I took the one less traveled by,
And that has made all the difference
.
156
For the historian, the implications of this are clear. As even Scriven has conceded:
[I]n history, given the data we have up to a certain point, there are a number of possible subsequent turns of fortune, none of which would seem to us inexplicable.... Inevitability is only in retrospect ...; and the inevitability of determinism is explanatory rather than predictive. Hence freedom of choice, which is between future alternatives, is not incompatible with the existence of causes for every event.... [W]e would have to ... abandon history if we sought to eliminate all surprise,
157
Chaos and the End of Scientific Determinism
There is a close (and far from accidental) parallel between the questioning of narrative determinism by writers like Musil and Borges and the questioning of classical Laplacian determinism by twentieth-century scientists. This is something which, regrettably, historians have tended to ignore (as E. H. Carr did when confronted by the theory of black holes), or simply to misunderstand. Thus a great many of those philosophers of history who have argued in this century about whether history was a ‘science’ seem not to have grasped that their notion of science was an out-of-date relic of the nineteenth century. What is more, if they had paid closer attention to what their scientific colleagues were actually doing, they would have been surprised - perhaps even pleased - to find that they were asking the wrong question. For it is a striking feature of a great many modern developments in the natural sciences that they have been fundamentally historical in character, in that they have been concerned with changes over time. Indeed, for this reason it is not wholly frivolous to turn the old question on its head and ask not ‘Is history a science?’ ‘but Is science history?’
This is true even of the relatively old second law of thermodynamics, which states that the entropy of an isolated system always increases - that is, that disorder will tend to increase if things are left to themselves, and that even attempts to create order have the ultimate effect of decreasing the amount of ordered energy available. This is of profound historical importance, not least because it implies an ultimate and
disorderly
end to the history of human life and indeed the universe. Einstein’s theory of relativity too has implications for historical thinking, since it dispenses with the notion of absolute time. After Einstein, we now realise that each observer has his own measure of time: were I to rise high above the earth, it would seem that events below were taking longer to happen because of the effect of the earth’s gravitational field on the speed of light. However, even relative time has only one direction or ‘arrow’, principally because of entropy and the effect of entropy on our psychological perception of time: even the energy expended in recording an event in our memory increases the amount of disorder in the universe.
Disorder increases. Nothing travels faster than light. Contrary to the expectations of nineteenth-century positivists, however, not every process in the natural world can be summed up in such clear-cut laws. One of the most important scientific developments of the late nineteenth century was the realisation that the majority of statements about the relationships between natural phenomena were no more than probabilistic in nature. Indeed, the American C. S. Peirce proclaimed the end of determinism as early as 1892 in his book
The Doctrine of Necessity Examined
: ‘Chance itself pours in at every avenue of sense: it is of all things the most obtrusive,’ declared Peirce. ‘Chance is First, Law is Second, the tendency to take habits is Third.’
158
Decisive evidence for this came in 1926 when Heisenberg demonstrated that it is impossible to predict the future position and velocity of a particle accurately, because its present position can only be measured using at least a quantum of light. The shorter the wavelength of light used, the more accurate the measurement of the particle’s position - but also the greater disturbance to its velocity. Because of this ‘uncertainty principle’, quantum mechanics can only predict a number of possible outcomes for a particular observation and suggest which is more likely. As Stephen Hawking has said, this ‘introduces an unavoidable element of unpredictability or randomness in science’ at the most fundamental level.
159
Indeed, it was precisely this which Einstein, faithful as he remained to the ideal of a Laplacian universe, found so objectionable. As he put it in his famous letter to Max Born:
You believe in the God who plays dice, and I in complete law and order in a world which objectively exists, and which I, in a wildly speculative way, am trying to capture. I firmly
believe
, but I hope that someone will find a more realistic way, or rather a more tangible basis than it has been my lot to do. Even the great initial success of the quantum theory does not make me believe in the fundamental dice game, although I am well aware that your younger colleagues interpret this as a consequence of senility.
160

Other books

The Ghost Feeler by Wharton, Edith
The Bradshaw Variations by Cusk, Rachel
Return to Me by Robin Lee Hatcher
The Long Game by Fynn, J. L.
Ali vs. Inoki by Josh Gross
The Sins of Lady Dacey by Marion Chesney
Cape Cod Promises: Love on Rockwell Island by Bella Andre, Melissa Foster