Paradiso (178 page)

Read Paradiso Online

Authors: Dante

BOOK: Paradiso
4.26Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

94.
   See Jacomuzzi (Jaco.1965.1), p. 10, discussing the tension in this canto between
letargo
(forgetting) and the frequent presence of verbs for seeing. And see Picone (Pico.1994.1), pp. 200–202.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

95.
   The word
impresa
(undertaking, enterprise) has an interesting history in the poem. See Hollander (Holl.1969.1), pp. 230–31, pointing out that, in
Inferno
II.41 and 47, the word refers to Dante’s journey and that, in
Inferno
XXXII.7, it represents Dante’s poem about that journey; here, on the other hand, it would seem to refer both to the journey and to the record of that journey, for the first is in process of becoming the second.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

96.
   According to Ovid, Jason was the builder of the first ship (“primaeque ratis molitor” [
Metam.
VIII.302]). For the history of the
Argo
-motif, see Curtius (Curt.1950.1), favoring Ovid (
Metam.
VII.120), which assuredly lies behind Dante’s earlier reference to Jason’s voyage (see the note to
Par.
II.17–18), but does not seem quite so good a fit here.

The image of Neptune looking up from beneath the sea is reminiscent of what the poet tells us in Canto XXXI.73–78, where he looked up at Beatrice as though he were immersed in the deepest point in the sea and she were at the highest point in the earth’s atmosphere. Both sightings involve the word
effige
(features), the first time as Beatrice’s likeness, the second (
Par.
XXXIII.131), that of Jesus. The fact that Neptune saw the shadow (
ombra
) of the
Argo
makes it at least probable that the poet hoped we would consider that voyage as the prefiguration of his own (see Hollander [Holl.1969.1], p. 232).

And as for Ovidian inspiration for what is sometimes considered a Dantean invention, Hollander (Holl.1969.1), p. 222, has argued for the impact of the last line (721) of Ovid’s Book VI, describing the
Argo
setting sail from Iolcos: “Per mare non notum prima petiere carina” (The first keel to cleave an unknown sea). That would leave Neptune alone unaccounted for. To be sure, we find him looking up from the seabed (wherever Dante found the source of the image) earlier in this very poem,
Inferno
XXVIII.83–84, where, in his only other appearance, he witnesses Malatestino’s treachery as he has witnessed similar crimes on the part of Greeks (
gente argolica
), the “bad Argonauts” succeeding Jason, as it were.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

97.
   
For Dante’s “sospesa,” Gilson (Gils.1924.1), p. 59, cites the prologue of Bonaventure’s
Itinerarium mentis in Deum
for a similar use of the word
suspensio
to denote the mind’s ecstatic rapture in its contemplation of God.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

98.
   When Dante looked at Beatrice in Eden, the angels cried out (
Purg.
XXXII.9) that he was “troppo fiso!” (too fixed), in the sense that he was confounding the physical and the spiritual in his appreciation of Beatrice. Now there can be no question of that, since “fixation” on God is the condition of blessedness for eternity, as the following two tercets make absolutely plain.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

100–105.
   Not only is the intellect satisfied by gazing on God, but the will is, too; for what other good, as object of the will, can supervene?
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

106–108.
   For a final time, the poet, having nearly completed a poem that has just reported having seen and understood the underlying principle ordering the entire universe, insists that, compared to the truth of that vision, his work is mere baby talk. (See the note to
Par.
XV.121–123 and Hollander [Holl.1980.2].)
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

111–114.
   Preparing us to see the Trinity through his eyes, the poet reassures us that he harbors no heretical notions about God’s nature(s); if He is three, that does not mean that He is other than one; if He is one, that does not mean that He is other than three. Even the protagonist’s vastly improved powers still have one more stage of visionary capacity to reach, one in which he will be able to experience the unchanging Trinity with his changed sight.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

115–117.
   The Trinity is first experienced as three circles inhering in a single space, distinguished only by their colors, not their sizes, which are identical.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

116–120.
   Bonanno (Bona.2001.1), p. 224, suggests that the rhymes here deliberately echo those found in
Donna me prega
, vv. 51–55 (
miri, tiri, giri
), with subversive intent, and indeed sees the entire final canto as entering into a corrective debate with the understanding of the nature of love proposed in Cavalcanti’s
canzone
.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

118–120.
   The tercet, as characterized by Carroll (comm. to vv. 115–123) as presenting “what Aquinas calls the Relations of Divinity according to
the Procession of Persons out of identity of substance—the Relations of Paternity, Generation and Spiration (
Summa
, I, q. 28). From the circle of the Father appeared reflected the circle of the Son, as Iris [rainbow] from Iris [rainbow]; and from both was breathed forth equally the fire of Love which is the Holy Spirit (on the Procession of the Spirit from both Father and Son, and the
filioque
controversy, see above [Carroll’s comm.], on
Par.
X.1–6). We must not think of these in the form of three rainbows one within another, or even as the three colours of a rainbow, for these are also one within another. The ‘one dimension’ shows that Dante conceived of them as co-existing in the one space, though he does not explain how he was able to see the three colours distinct within each other.” One supposes that they manifested themselves as changing colors. Dante does not assign a particular color either to Father or Son; the Holy Spirit, as Love, is understandably red.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

121.
   For this last use of
fioco
(weak, indistinct) in the poem, see Hollander (Holl.1983.1), tying together
Vita nuova
XXIII (see pp. 76–77),
Inferno
I.63, and this verse (pp. 150–51). For a similar view, see Bologna (Bolo.2002.1), p. 461. Torraca seems to have been the first commentator (and, among those gathered in the DDP, he seems to have been followed only by Mestica [comm. to this tercet]) even to note that we have seen this term before in
Inferno
I.63, but has no further comment. Hollander suggests that “this use of the word is intended to make us consider Virgil’s initial
fiochezza
, with all its metaphoric insistence on the fact that he had failed to speak the Word. In this respect, the two poets find themselves once again together at the end, reunited in their failures, and yet so very far from one another, separated by the ground of their failures” (p. 151).

Bellomo (Bell.1996.1), p. 55n., believes that the question of Dante’s Virgil needs to be reopened, beginning with a rereading of Bruno Nardi (Nard.1960.1), especially pp. 96–150.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

124–126.
   Ledda (Ledd.2002.1), p. 317n., says he is following Jacomuzzi in seeing that the protagonist’s final vision is of the Incarnation, and not the Trinity. Does one really have to make that choice? It would seem to be preferable to see it as Trinitarian, which includes the vision of Jesus as spirit in flesh, as He is.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

127–132.
   Finally, Dante sees the Humanity of the Trinity, the Son, Jesus Christ, incarnate within the circle that abstractly represents the Second Person. Once again the differing colors of the Persons are insisted on, and once
again (see the note to vv. 118–120) Dante does not report the color of the Son (nor of the Father).

It took centuries until a commentator (Scartazzini [comm. to verse 131]) realized that this image contained a reference to St. Paul (Philippians 2:7), “but made himself nothing, taking the form of a servant, being born in the likeness of men.” This is currently a fairly widespread perception, but the only other writer in the DDP to observe it is Grandgent (comm. to verse 131).

The enormous presence of the Bible in the poem has at times simply overwhelmed its observers. This is a case in point. Moore (Moor.1896.1), pp. 321–34, lists over six hundred possible citations in all Dante’s works, the bulk of them in the
Commedia
. Thus one needs to deal cautiously with Steiner’s accountancy (Stei.2001.1), p. 89, which counts the actual citations (rather than more general forms of reference) as two in
Inferno
, eight in
Purgatorio
, and a dozen in
Paradiso
.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

127.
   This is the final use of this word, whether as an abstract noun meaning “concept” or “conceiving” or a transitive verb (to conceive [an idea—see
Inf.
XII.13 for the first and only use of the verb to mean “to conceive offspring,” although there is more than an overtone of that sense here]). There have been twelve previous uses of the noun or of the verb (
Inf.
XXVI.73, XXXII.4;
Par.
III.60, XV.41, XVIII.86, XIX.12, XXII.33, XXIV.60, XXIX.81 and 132, XXXIII.68 and 122), which has more uses in this canto than in any other (three). See the note to
Paradiso
XV.40–42. See also Ledda (Ledd.2002.1), pp. 316–19.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

130–132.
   See Dronke (Dron.1965.1), pp. 389–90, and Baranski (Bara. 2000.1), pp. 173–74, 217, both cited by Gilson (Gils.2004.1), p. 174n., as synthesizing Platonism and Aristotelianism.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

131.
   For notice of a possible reflection here of the fourth and final stage of loving God in St. Bernard’s
De diligendo Deo
, see Hollander (Holl.1976.2), p. 35 (repr. Holl.1980.2): “Commentators have for a long time annotated this passage with a reference to Philippians 2:7” (as we have seen [note to vv. 127–132], that is barely true; only two of them in the last 150 years). Hollander goes on to show that Bernard, in
De diligendo Deo
(
Sancti Bernardi Opera
, ed. J. Leclercq and H. M. Rochais, Vol. III [Rome: Editiones Cistercienses, 1963], p. 142), resorts to the same Pauline passage in a highly similar context, describing the height of the mystical love of God, when one loves oneself in God. For Bernard’s four stages in
the love of God and their possible relation to the stages in the
Comedy
(first suggested by a student at Princeton, Donald J. Mathison, in 1968), see the note to
Purgatorio
XXVII.139–141. For later discussions that are in agreement, see Mazzoni (Mazz.1997.1), p. 176, as well as Moevs (Moev.2005.1), p. 81. And see E. G. Gardner (Gard.1913.1), p. 118, for the relation of
De diligendo Deo
X.27–28 to Dante’s spiritual preparedness for the final vision.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

133.
   For a study of this penultimate simile, a meditation on how Dante may be said to have “squared the circle,” see Herzman and Towsley (Herz.1994.1). See also Ledda (Ledd.2002.1), p. 317n.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

137–138.
   See Kay (Kay.2002.1), pp. 30–31, for the notion, advanced as a follow-up to his examination of the Vitruvian nature of Dante’s calculations of the dimensions of both the giants (
Inf.
XXX) and of Satan (
Inf.
XXXIV), that what Dante sees is Vitruvius’s image of man inscribed in a circle, his
umbelicus
at the center of the circle, his fingers and toes at the circumference, in what is the eventual model for Leonardo da Vinci’s far more famous design. As charming as this notion is, the word
effige
in Dante (
Par.
XXXI.77, XXXIII.131) seems rather to indicate, as is generally the case in Italian, the visage, not the whole human body.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

138.
   Jacomuzzi (Jaco.1965.1) offers a reading of these verses and of the poem as a whole in the mode of a theologically determined fourfold allegoresis. For discussion, with some bibliography, of Italian and American treatments of theological allegory in the poem, see Hollander (Holl. 2001.1), pp. 37–39 and p. 188, nn. 55–57.
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

139–141.
   For insistence on the role played, in this final vision, of both the
Benjamin major
of Richard of St. Victor and the
Itinerarium mentis in Deum
of Bonaventure, see Gilson (Gils.1924.1), pp. 56–57. Gilson (pp. 62–63) concludes that, given these two sources, Dante’s vision is not a Pauline
raptus
(a function of the intellect), but a Franciscan
exstasis
(a function of the affective capacity). This, however, and despite Gilson’s authority, is not the general current opinion, which rather insists that Dante did have a Pauline
raptus
(as the entire
cantica
has been preparing us to grant). For instance, Güntert (Gunt.2002.2), p. 507, cites Aquinas (
ST
II–II, q. 175, a. 3), distinguishing among three kinds of vision (but for an earlier and similar treatment see Pertile [Pert.1981.1], pp. 6–7). After discussions that are in strong agreement with positions taken on the issues by Augustine, Thomas
explains, in his Reply to Objection 1: “Man’s mind is rapt by God to the contemplation of divine truth in three ways. First, so that he contemplates it through certain imaginary pictures (
per similitudines quasdam imaginarias
), and such was the ecstasy that came upon Peter [Acts 10:10–16]. Secondly, so that he contemplates the divine truth through its intelligible effects (
per intelligibiles effectus
); such was the ecstasy of David, who said (Psalm 115 [116]:11): ‘I said in my excess: Every man is a liar.’ Thirdly, so that he contemplates it in its essence (
in sua essentia
). Such was the rapture of Paul, as also of Moses; and not without reason, since as Moses was the first Teacher of the Jews, so was Paul the first ‘Teacher of the gentiles’ ” (tr. from the website of the
Catholic Encyclopedia
). It is typical of Gilson, a Dominican himself, to downplay the importance of Dominicans in favor of Franciscans. His graciousness is a model to us all. However, it may be that he is simply incorrect here. The reader will note that here, even at the conclusion of the great poem, commentators are divided among Franciscan and Dominican positions on the issues. For the difficult history of the intertwined strands of knowledge and love in St. Thomas, in whom, at least apparently, such distinctions would be clearer than they are in Dante, see Sherwin (Sher.2005.1). In Dante, we find at moments, like this one, knowledge eclipsing the claims of love; at others, that dynamic would seem to be reversed. One comes away with the feeling that Dante responds fully to the main competing voices in this continuing dialectic, “Franciscans” (Francis himself, Bonaventure, Bernard, and perhaps Joachim as well), who privilege love (but not
against
knowledge), and “Dominicans” (Thomas
primissimus inter impares
, but Albertus Magnus and Remigius Girolamus as well), who privilege knowledge (but not
against
love). For an article that strongly supports the notion that Dante was closely aware of the text of Ezechiel, see Bognini (Bogn.2007.1).
[return to
English
/
Italian
]

Other books

Double Prey by Steven F. Havill
By These Ten Bones by Clare B. Dunkle
Hollywood Lies by N.K. Smith
A Step Farther Out by Jerry Pournelle
The Thirteenth Man by J.L. Doty
Hearts Aflame by Johanna Lindsey
A Little Training by Abbie Adams
Caribbean's Keeper by Boland, Brian;