| 58. Rapaczynski, Nature and Politics , p. 279.
|
| 59. Rommen, Natural Law , p. 89.
|
| 60. Von Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Society , p. 113.
|
| 61. Tuck, Natural Rights Theories , pp. 175, 177.
|
| 62. Macpherson, Political Theory of Possessive Individualism , p. 262 passim.
|
| 63. John Dunn, The Political Thought of John Locke (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969; reprint, 1975), p. xi.
|
| 64. Dunn, Political Thought of John Locke , p. 263. Dunn draws a sober conclusion on p. 267: "We have, it seems, come to accept in the broadest of terms the politics of Locke but, while doing so, we have firmly discarded the reasons which alone made them acceptable even to Locke. It is hard to believe that this combination can be quite what we need today."
|
| 65. Skinner, Foundations of Modern Political Thought , vol. 2, p. 174.
|
| 66. Troeltsch, "Ideas of Natural Law and Humanity," p. 208.
|
| 67. James Gordon Clapp, "John Locke," Encyclopedia of Philosophy , ed. P. Edwards, vol. 4 (New York: Macmillan, 1967), p. 502.
|
| 68. Abrams, John Locke , p. 78.
|
| 69. See the discussion of Babington, Rule of Law in Britain , pp. 15758.
|
|